|
Polis
and Cosmos
Lecture delivered to Canterbury Christ Church University
6 October 2018
Joseph Milne
There are aspects of our human experience that always have deep
symbolic roots and which shape our way of life even if we do not
notice. One such aspect is the symbolic relation between our conception
of the universe and our conception of human society. There is always
in any culture a correspondence between the vision of the cosmos
and its order, and the vision of society and its order. We are living
at a time when this is not generally acknowledged, and so it has
become invisible. To many it would seem quite strange to suggest
that our contemporary conception of the universe has any political
or social implications. In part this is because it is assumed that
our scientific knowledge of the universe disposes of any symbolic
understanding of it. And likewise with the scientific approaches
to the study of society, especially those that are strongly mathematical
and statistical. There would seem to be no scope for any symbolic
understanding of this kind of knowledge. However, I wish to suggest
that our modern empirical approach to understanding the universe
and society has behind it deep symbolic roots, and that how we now
conceive human society and civilisation is deeply connected with
our conception of the universe.
There
are reasons why most people would find this difficult to accept,
but these I shall come to later. To understand our present vision
of society and the cosmos we need to go back to a time when the
symbolic relations between different orders of reality were part
of the general outlook of the culture. This we find in the ancient
creation myths from all parts of the world. The first impulse to
'story telling' is to say how all things came to be. Despite the
infinite variety of creation myths, they all say 'it came to pass
that the world and human beings came into being in this way'. It
may be that God spoke and all things began. Or it may be that the
world hatched from a primordial egg. Or it may be that man sprang
out of a peapod. Or it may even be that some evil demiurge created
the world in order to imprison immortal souls in darkness and ignorance.
These mythic narratives all serve the purpose of situating our human
existence in the cosmic order. They are not meant to be understood
literally. They are consciously metaphorical and even magical, and
this is because they express the mystery of the beginning of things,
not with a view to explaining how things came to be, but rather
to express our awe and wonder that existence has come about. This
wonder and awe is the wellspring of piety and religion, and of philosophy
and the arts. Piety, religion, philosophy and art are our response
to finding the world has come into being. The world makes us open
our eyes and calls for us to make a reply in word and deed. How
we live is our reply, both individually and as society.
It
is really important to see that these myths are not intended to
give an explanation of the world, but rather provoke a response.
In a sense they are already a response because they marvel at the
coming to be of the world, and they bring us to stand before all
that is, like Adam brought by God before the beasts and the herbs
of the field to name them. And in naming the animals and growing
things of the earth Adam commits to a way of life with them - because
naming is also making a bond. There is a sacramental element in
naming, and that is why it can also be impious or blasphemous. The
manner in which we speak of things shapes our souls.
I
suggested that this mythical apprehension of things, which finds
expression in the mythical canon of a culture, is the wellspring
of religion and philosophy. These two modes of response to the coming
to be of the cosmos take their own distinctive forms and adopt their
own distinctive kinds of language. The religious manifestation takes
the form of theology, where the symbols of the divine are retained,
and where a conscious vocabulary of divine metaphors remain in use.
And so God is a 'person', and the divine nature a trinity of persons.
This theological language not only speaks of the divine realm and
source of things, it also addresses it and speaks the language of
prayer. The philosophical manifestation takes the form of metaphysics,
where the intellectual language of abstraction is born. So rather
than speak of the Father, as the theologian does, the philosopher
speaks of the One or the Good or the True or the Absolute. These
two modes of response and understanding have a very complex historical
relationship with each other. They flourish when both discourses
exist together in a society. They decline when divorced from each
other. In truly remarkable thinkers, such as Plato, we see how in
the dialogues he moves from one to the other, though never confusing
them. The same may be said of Thomas Aquinas.
Nevertheless,
both modes of understanding seek to discern the relationship of
the human realm and the cosmic order. For the ancients human society
maintains its own nature through being brought into accord with
the heavenly order. For Plato there is a correspondence between
the cosmos, the city, and the citizen. The city, the natural human
dwelling place, governed by speech, is a small cosmos after the
pattern of the great cosmos, and the individual citizen is a small
city after the pattern of the great city. For Plato this means that
the polis takes form through a combination of correspondences between
the divine cosmic order and the order of the soul. In one sense
the polis is a microcosmos, and in another sense it is a macroanthropos,
the soul write large. The polis flourishes in peace when its laws
spring from and embody this threefold harmony. Then the citizens
love the laws, and education and the arts nurture the natural order
of the soul. The opposite condition is where the city splits into
factions and is at war with itself, and where chaos threatens to
overthrow the natural order.
Plato's
endless enquiry into politics - the question of virtuous citizenship
- seeks to understand the connections between the order of the whole
universe and the human city and the human soul. These three need
to be thought about together. It is often said that Plato is the
father of political enquiry, yet it is clear that this correlation
between the cosmos, the city and the soul was present in ancient
Egyptian ethics. In her study of Egyptian Maat, Maulana Karenga,
writes:
Assman
(LA IV, 974) has noted concerning the person in Kemetic society
that "As an individual man is not viable (lebenfahig): he lives
in and through society." This essentially means that the Maatian
community is a communitarian and participatory moral community.
Here always the person-in-relationship, i.e., in family, community,
society, is the centre of focus as distinct from modern European
individualism, in which the individual, abstract, autonomous and
often alienated, is the essential focus and center of gravity. In
Maatian ethics the sociality of selfhood is defined by roles and
relationships and the practice attached to these roles. Self-development
becomes a communal act, an act rooted in activity for and of the
community. One, then, is not an individual, autonomous and alone,
but a person interrelated and encumbered by the relations and demands
of one's society.
Maulana
further remarks that "the Maatian society was not simply a
human construction, but also a participant in the divine and cosmic
ideal and practice of Maat". Again "humans are embedded
in this order with its divine, social and natural aspects. In their
identity as children and images of God, humans belong to the divine;
in their identity as social beings, they belong to society; and
in their identity as living beings they belong to nature".
Similar
threefold divisions of participation resonate in Plato and into
Stoicism and the Christian natural law tradition. The ethical dimension
of life is manifest on all levels, from the divine cosmic order
down to the laws of nature, and the human city embodies all aspects.
The work of philosophy and theology is to articulate 'the whole'
to which human life belongs if it is to flourish. For while everyone
has a sense of the whole, without reflection it remains indistinct.
Connected
with the sense of the whole is the question of the hierarchical
nature of the cosmic order. The threefold division of divine, social,
and natural in Maat ethics is a clear hierarchy, descending from
highest to lowest. It is a sacred order, which is what the word
'hierarchy' means. For Plato an acknowledgement of the hierarchical
order of the cosmos is essential for understanding human society
and for law-making. One of the great dangers for the polis is that
the cosmic hierarchy should be inverted, placing the least ordered
and intelligent first in the order of things coming into being,
and the highest intelligence and knowledge as last in coming into
being. To adopt such a view is at once arrogant and impious. In
Plato's last dialogue, the Laws, Plato portrays an imaginary youth
who expresses such a view, and he imagines what might be said to
such a youth:
Let
us say to the youth: The ruler of the universe has ordered all things
with a view to the excellence and preservation of the whole, and
each part, as far as may be, has an action and passion appropriate
to it. Over these, down to the least fraction of them, ministers
have been appointed to preside, who have wrought out their perfection
with infinitesimal exactness. And one of these portions of the universe
is thine own, unhappy man, which, however little, contributes to
the whole; and you do not seem to be aware that this and every other
creation is for the sake of the whole, and in order that the life
of the whole may be blessed; and that you are created for the sake
of the whole, and not the whole for the sake of you. For every physician
and every skilled artist does all things for the sake of the whole,
directing his effort towards the common good, executing the part
for the sake of the whole, and not the whole for the sake of the
part. And you are annoyed because you are ignorant how what is best
for you happens to you and to the universe, as far as the laws of
the common creation admit.
The
impiety of this imaginary youth lies in him supposing he is the
centre of existence, and that the universe exists for his sake,
and not him for the sake of the good of the whole. For the ancient
philosophers such an introverted view of things is the root of all
ignorance. From such a position there cannot be any real enquiry
into the nature of things, or into the true nature of society. Plato
suggests that there are several false positions that can arise from
this false conception of the hierarchical whole. The first is that
the gods do not exist. The second is that the gods came into being
later in the emergence of things from unintelligent elements. The
third is that the gods may be persuaded to act contrary to their
wisdom and grant things to men unjustly. These three 'impious' beliefs
preclude the proper investigation of the nature of the polis and
the human soul. They alienate the human order from the divine order.
This is because the rightly ordered polis reflects in its institutions
and laws the greater order of the cosmos. But also the soul of the
individual citizen cannot be harmonious with itself without being
ordered harmoniously with the divine order of the heavens, as Plato
shows in the Timaeus. This is because the motions of intelligence
of the soul become properly ordered when attuned to the divine harmony
of the heavens. This is the foundation of the theory that the mind
grasps the truth of things through conforming itself to truth. Also,
the harmonious order of the soul brings the rational, the spirited
and the appetitive parts into their proper relations serving their
proper ends. As for the individual, so for the city. The harmony
of the city is maintained through honouring the highest things first,
and the least things last. Thus Plat says in the Laws:
We
say, then, that the likelihood is that if a city is to be preserved
and is to become happy within the limits of human power, it must
necessarily apportion honours and dishonours correctly. The correct
apportionment is one which honours most the good things pertaining
to the soul (provided it has moderation), second, the beautiful
and good things pertaining to the body, and, third, the things said
to accrue from property and money. If some lawgiver or city steps
outside this ranking either by promoting money to a position of
honour or by raising one of the lesser things to a more honourable
status, he will do a deed that is neither pious nor statesmanlike.
(697b)
This
ranking of honours applies to the individual soul and to the city.
It is analogous to the threefold division of the soul Plato draws
in the Republic of the rational, spirited, and appetitive. Owing
to such analogical correspondences, Plato derives the hierarchical
nature of the polis from the hierarchical nature of the soul, where
the higher governs the lower. Thus Socrates says in the Republic:
In
that case, my friend, if the individual too has these same elements
in his soul, we shall feel entitled to expect that it is because
these elements are in the same condition in him as they were in
the city that he is properly titled by the same names we gave the
city. (435b-c)
The
ranking of parts in the individual soul and in the polis does not
imply inequality. It implies proportion and harmony between the
different parts of the soul or different functions of the institutions
of the polis. For example, when the things pertaining to the rational
part of the soul are most honoured, this means that reason regulates
the spirited part of the soul so that courage is measured and not
foolhardy, or the appetitive part of the soul so that eating is
healthful. In other words, reason acts in different ways in different
parts of the soul, and likewise in the polis. It follows from this
also that any ills that befall the polis from within are due to
these proportions being disrupted.
This
raises what for many is the most controversial aspect of Plato's
correlation of the soul and the polis: that the laws of the city
are intended to regulate both the institutions of the polis and
the souls of it citizens. Plato assumes, contrary to modern politics,
that there is a natural order of the city which it should strive
to approximate. Aristotle assumes the same. Our age finds this assumption
difficult because the city, and indeed civilisation, are considered
to be artificial constructs and not part of nature. In considering
the soul or society our age no longer acknowledges a correspondence
between soul, polis, and cosmos. The true and final aim of law-making
is friendship, as Plato says in the Laws: "When we asserted
one should look toward moderation, or prudence, or friendship, these
goals are not different but the same". There is a remarkable
passage in Plato's Laws which argues that only when the common good
is sought is the political art practiced wisely:
For,
in the first place, it is difficult to know that the true political
art must care not for the private but for the common - for the common
binds cities together, while the private tears them apart - and
that it is in the interest of both the common and the private that
the common, rather than the private be established nobly.
In
a way, it is only when citizens seek the common good that they are
truly citizens.
The understanding that the polis is part of the greater order of
nature passes on from Plato and Aristotle to the Stoics. The Stoics
emphasise the cosmic aspect in particular, especially the understanding
of the cosmos as intelligent and wise. Cicero, for example, records
the philosophy of the Stoics in his On the Nature of the Gods, where
he writes:
.
. . One can also see that the cosmos contains intelligence from
the fact that it is without doubt better than any other nature.
Just as there is no part of our body which is not of less value
than we ourselves are, so the cosmos as a whole must be of more
value than any part of it. But if this is so, the cosmos must necessarily
be wise, for if it were not, then human beings, who are part of
the cosmos, would have to be of more value than the entire cosmos
in virtue of participation in reason.
As
with Plato, the Stoics see the connection between the cosmos and
the soul through the participating of both in reason. Reason, or
intelligence, is the ordering principle of the cosmos and the soul,
guiding everything to its proper end in relation to the perfection
of the whole. From the correspondence, the Stoics speak of two cities,
one the universe, the dwelling place of the gods, the other the
human city. Insofar as human beings act wisely and virtuously, they
dwell in both cities at once. Again, no one speaks of this more
eloquently than Cicero:
.
. . the universe is as it were a city consisting of gods and men,
the gods exercising leadership, the men subordinate. Community exists
between them because they partake of reason, which is natural law;
and all else has come into being for their sake. In consequence
of which it must be believed that the god who administers the whole
exercises providence for men, being beneficent, kind, well-disposed
to men, just and having all the virtues.
This
passage is interesting as it bridges the philosophical and the theological
modes of understanding. To speak of the universe as providential
and 'just and having all the virtues' is a theological mode of speech,
and it enables a perception of the goodness of the cosmos. It means
that the proper human life of dwelling in the cosmic and the human
city is also 'just and having all the virtues'. The life of virtue
is also the life in accord with 'natural law' - a concept that was
to resonate through the Middle Ages and into jurisprudence and the
English common law tradition. The natural law is the law that belongs
to everything by nature and which inclines each created being towards
its proper function and completion. It manifests in the human soul
and in the community as the virtues, as in this Stoic description:
The
goal of all these virtues is to live consistently with nature. Each
one enables a human being to achieve this [goal] in his own way;
for [a human] has from nature inclinations to discover what is appropriate
and to stabilize his impulses and to stand firm and to distribute
[fairly]. And each of the virtues does what is consonant [with these
inclinations] and does its own job, thus enabling a human being
to live consistently with nature.
The
approach to human life through the natural law and the virtues stands
in strong contrast to the positivist ethics that emerged in the
seventeenth century, which speaks of rights and rational principles
of morality, which is an ethics operating from outside the soul.
Natural law and the virtues understand ethics as arising from the
natural order and inclinations of the soul, not as 'rules' to follow
but as qualities of authentic being, as for example in 'courage'
or 'prudence' or 'temperance'. These virtues arise from the harmony
of the soul with itself and with the cosmos. The human being is
naturally good when acting according to its true nature. Positivist
ethics, on the other hand, assumes a conflict between human nature
and right action. It is not a new position. It is an opinion strongly
opposed by Plato in the sophists who held that virtuous action was
useful only in public where it served one's advantage, while in
private it could be discarded and one could follow any inclination
or desire without fear of retribution from the gods. It is the core
of the eighteenth century economic idea of 'enlightened self-interest'.
I mention this contrast because the positivist ethics has no cosmic
dimension. It does not situate the human person within 'the whole'
of reality, even in a materialist sense, let alone in a divine sense.
Because of this many of the cosmic symbols, both in religious and
civic life, which articulated our relation with the cosmos are losing
their meaning. The pantheon of the gods, the hierarchy of angels,
the scales of justice, the sacred precinct, the harmony of the spheres,
rites of passage - all these symbolic connections of the city with
the heavens are losing their power and capacity to orient the soul
towards the greater whole and greater good.
The
correspondence between soul, polis and cosmos takes new form in
the Christian tradition. St Augustine's City of God portrays human
citizenship as dwelling in two cities, the earthly or temporal city
and the heavenly or eternal city, resonating with the Stoic conception
mentioned earlier. The eternal or heavenly city now becomes the
Christian community, which is the membership of the body of Christ
or the ecclesia. The two cities now bring a new distinction. The
heavenly city is ruled by divine law, the earthly by human law.
Although the earthly city in some sense reflects the divine law,
that law cannot be fulfilled in the earthly city. Again, distinct
from the Stoic city, the soul is called beyond the mortal life of
this world to the eternal life of the divine world. This also means
that for the Christian citizen there is an inner spiritual life,
and an outer secular life. This turn inwards, which opens the way
for the Christian mystical tradition, reconciles the Christian life
with life in the Roman republic and the Roman pantheon.
We
cannot go into it here, but we see in Augustine a great reconciliation
between Greek philosophy, Roman Stoicism, Judaism, and the New Testament.
The emergent mystical element is also to found in Neoplatonism,
especially Plotinus. But while Plotinus and Neoplatonism generally
maintains the metaphysical and intellectual mode of speech and understanding,
Christianity develops the theological and symbolic mode of speech
and understanding.
This
opens the door to a new and marvellously rich tradition of symbolism.
At the heart of Christianity is the revelation of Scripture, which
is at once literal and mystical. St Augustine, following a tradition
already initiated by Origen and Clement of Alexandria, saw Scripture
as having a threefold sense - the literal, the allegorical and the
mystical. But unlike the tendency in the Neoplatonic approach to
Homer and the Greek Pantheon, in which the allegorical sense negates
the literal sense, Augustine likens Scripture to a human being,
having a body, soul and spirit, equivalent to the literal, allegorical,
and mystical senses. These three senses all belong, and a higher
sense does not displace or discard a lower sense. The reason for
this is that Scripture is symbolic of the Incarnation of Christ
- for at the heart of Christianity is the mystery of the Eternal
becoming temporal, the Infinite becoming finite, the Invisible becoming
visible. The Son of God became human. The Uncreated and the Created
became one. Seen in this way, the created world, which is the work
of God, now becomes hierophanic, shining with divine life and meaning.
As Ricoeur says in his essay 'Manifestation and Proclamation':
That
a stone or a tree may manifest the sacred means that this profane
reality becomes something other than itself while still remaining
itself. It is transformed into something supernatural.
In
a new way, the vision of multiple levels of meaning in Scripture
is a return to the ancient vision of the cosmos as a living intelligence,
as manifesting wisdom through the natural order. With the threefold
division of meaning, analogous to the human form, it also represents
a reinterpretation of the correspondence between the soul and the
cosmos. Thus, for example, Origen says:
Since,
therefore, Scripture itself consists, as it were, of a body that
is perceived, of a soul which is understood and conceived to be
in the body, and of a spirit according to the shadow of the heavenly
things, come, then, let us invoke him who made the body, soul, and
spirit of Scripture, a body for those who have preceded us, a soul
for us, and a spirit for those who are destined to possess eternal
life in a future age and to arrive at the heavenly truth of the
law.
It
is clear that the three senses form a whole, without one sense negating
another sense, or one level overriding another. The body that is
perceived manifests truth visibly, the soul that is apprehended
manifests truth intellectually, and the spirit made present by grace
manifests truth mystically. All three meanings belong and are meant
to be apprehended. Indeed, we find later in the monastic tradition
an insistence on understanding the bodily or literal sense fully
before seeking the other senses. Novices are reprimanded for 'inventing'
allegorical meanings of their own out of intellectual pride. There
is an insistence that the Scriptures are approached with piety and
devotion, because only then is the soul able to receive gifts of
grace. This attitude of piety, we recall, is what Plato also insisted
upon for a truthful understanding of the order of the cosmos and
the polis. Perception of the different levels of meaning depends
upon the virtuous ennoblement of the soul, and in a way it would
be more correct to speak of different levels of understanding rather
than different objects of perception.
With
this in mind, here is a passage from Hugh of St Victor's On Sacred
Scripture and its Authors teaching how one ought to attend to Scripture:
The
diligent examiner of Sacred Scripture should never neglect the meanings
of things. Just as our knowledge of primary things comes through
words, so too through the meaning of these things we come to understand
what is perceived in a spiritual way and our knowledge of these
things is made complete. The philosopher, in other kinds of writings,
comes to know only the meaning of words, but in Sacred Scripture
the meaning of things is much more excellent than the meaning of
words. The first is established by usage, but the second is dictated
by nature. The first is the voice of human beings, but the second
is the voice of God speaking to human beings. The meaning of words
is established by human convention, but the meaning of things is
determined by nature; and, by the will of the Creator, certain things
are signified by other things. The meaning of things is much more
manifold than the meaning of words. Few words have more than two
or three meanings, but a thing can mean as many other things as
it has visible or invisible properties in common with other things.
This
is a remarkable passage. Our modern tendency in reading is to suppose
that words give us the concept of things. But Hugh here insists
that the meaning is not in the concept of the word, but in the 'things'
the words speak of - what in modern hermeneutics is called the 'referent'.
So when Scripture speaks of the hills or herbs, the sea or the sky,
the rivers or the stars, it is these things themselves that have
meaning. These things are 'dictated by nature' and are 'the voice
of God speaking to human beings'. The things of the created world
are, as it were, the vocabulary of God, and are the speech of God,
the Word incarnate. So we find in the Cistercians of the twelfth
century a new birth of the most ancient hierophanic vision of nature,
where the profane is transformed into the sacred, yet without losing
its original created nature. The Scriptures are written in the language
of nature, quite distinct from the language of philosophy, and have
the power to guide the soul of the contemplative reader to the mystical
truth that is the true presence and meaning of the created world.
©
2018 Joseph Milne
|
"Moral
acts and human acts are one and the same thing." (Thomas
Aquinas, ST 1a2ae, q. 1, a. 3, c.)
|
|