Ownership
in Early Christianity
and the Natural Law Tradition
A
talk given at Henry George Foundation, London 2018
Joseph
Milne
Charles
Avilas book Ownership: Early Christian Teaching shows
us that the Church Fathers addressed the question of land ownership
and its exploitation very strongly. For example Avila quotes from
Saint Ambrose, Bishop of Milan, in the fourth century who wrote:
The
elements have been granted to all for their use. Rich and poor
alike enjoy the splendid ornaments of the universe. . . The house
of God is common to all. (p. 72)
In
another passage Ambrose says:
Thus
God has created everything in such a way that all things be possessed
in common. Nature therefore is the mother of common right, usurpation
of private right. (p. 74)
Ambroses
assertion that the earth and all the elements belong to all in common
is to be found in the other Church Fathers. It was an essential
part of early Christian thought. From the Christian perspective
all nature belongs to the Creator who has given it, simply as a
gift, to all the creatures to share in common. Just as God has created
each being, so likewise he has created their dwelling place, where
all may flourish with each other. With the human race this is even
more so, since through intelligent cooperation the community may
enhance the gifts of nature in mutual benefit, so there is no need
for want or poverty. This is the true state of nature
contrary to the atomistic doctrine of Hobbes.
According
to Ambrose, the cause of poverty is avarice. Very simply, it is
the desire to possess for oneself what by nature is to be shared
amongst all. Here he accuses the wealthy landlords as avaricious
who exploit their tenant farmers who barely survive while they themselves
live in luxurious palaces, gathering riches for their own sake.
Their defence, according to Avila, is the Roman law of property.
But
to Ambrose, and from a Christian perspective, gathering wealth as
an end in itself is to live for the wrong reason, out of accord
with nature, and to wilfully inflict harm on others. Like the other
Church Fathers, Ambrose pleads with the landed rich to give their
excess to the poor. This would be no more than to return what they
have stolen from them. On being elected Bishop of Milan by popular
demand, Ambrose gave most of his property to the poor.
Needless
to say, beyond a few rich Christians who heeded these pleas from
the Fathers, the exploitation of the land remained. And since the
wealth of the Roman Empire derived primarily from agriculture, the
direct abuse of land monopoly was a plainly evident wrong. Now it
is worth asking why this teaching of the early Church went largely
unheeded. Christianity, we should remember, became the official
religion of Rome, and these teachings widely known, especially the
idea of the community holding all in common and giving any excess
wealth to the poor.
We
are faced with the same question today. Why, after such great popularity,
have the insights of Henry George into the proper use of land also
gone unheeded? After all, as Charles Avila points out, George was
only saying in economic terms what the early church was saying in
ethical terms. The Fathers called upon the justice of divine providence,
George upon empirical economic justice. Both arrive at the same
evident truth: that if the gifts of nature are misappropriated,
then exploitation will arise between citizens, poverty will increase
while wealth increases and, if this is not remedied, a society will
eventually destroy itself as did the Roman Empire.
Now
Avila wonders why the slaves or tenants did not rise up against
the powerful landowners. It seems there were small rebellions, but
these were easily put down with force. If we look around the world
today, it is clear that the oppressed have no chance of remedying
their condition themselves. It is precisely because they are at
a disadvantage that they are oppressed. But if we turn to what we
may call the modern free democracies, it is equally clear that the
disadvantaged or exploited there are also the least likely to rise
up and bring about justice. A more likely result of any rebellion
is that the oppressed will become the oppressors just as
those fleeing to America from the Irish potato famine have done
through taking land-ownership with them. Avarice and injustice seem
to take root even from the best intentions.
Why
is it, then, that the more educated and influential cannot bring
about a remedy to this most basic injustice of misappropriating
the earth? Even those politicians who understand the land question
cannot bring about any change. All they can do is try to mitigate
the consequences of injustice.
Here
is where I believe the Church Fathers and the classical philosophers
had an insight which our own age lacks. They understood the human
situation at a far deeper level than either the poor or the rich
and powerful of their day. They could see that neither the rich
nor the poor understood human nature or the laws of nature
what we may call, along with Henry George, the social laws
of nature.
From
the Christian perspective, the question is: why does avarice arise?
Indeed, why does possessiveness arise? Why do human
beings desire to take things as their own property, even when it
obviously harms others? Is humanity selfish and brutal by nature
as Thomas Hobbes proposed in his Leviathan? Or, further,
is there no such thing as justice in the order of nature,
but merely brute force, survival of the fittest, and the war
of all against all? Is divine justice no more than a fiction
invented by the powerful in order to impose their rule on the weak,
as the Sophists argued in Platos time?
The
early Christians, like the classical philosophers before them, asked
these questions, and they rejected the idea that human nature is
essentially selfish. Christianity sees human nature as fallen from
its original natural or innocent state. It has always
been concerned with restoring human nature to its natural condition
its condition before the Fall. This meant that the political
or social teaching of the early Church, and in the Middle Ages,
recognised that there cannot be a truly just society in the fallen
human condition. What is required is a transformation of the soul,
so that the providential order of nature can again be perceived.
The
earliest Christian communities did attempt to live in common and
share all property. And this became the basis of monastic life
to live without any possessions. Yet even the monasteries tended
to accumulate wealth and every now and then needed great reform,
as with the birth of the Cistercians, Franciscans and Dominicans.
But it was recognised that the majority cannot live this way. We
will come back to how this was answered in a moment.
The
philosophers had a different explanation. They saw the problem lay
in errors of judgement, of mistaking for true what was not true.
This is how Plato and Aristotle saw the human situation. According
to them we do not know how to judge correctly between the true and
the false, or between the just and the unjust. They understand that
the faculties of the mind are naturally directed towards truth,
just as the eye is directed towards light, or the ear towards sound,
but that this capacity needs to be developed through careful education.
This meant strengthening the rational faculties, but also the body,
and the cultivation of the virtues primarily justice, courage,
prudence, and temperance. For Plato and Aristotle, the understanding
of the truth of things is directly connected with understanding
justice. For them enquiry into the true and the good cannot be separated.
Book
I of Platos Republic is all about misconceptions of
justice. These take several forms. First, that justice is only an
external convention in a society. Second, that justice is the rule
of the strong over the weak. Third, that it is doing good to your
friends and harm to your enemies. Fourth, that it is giving to each
what they are owed. Each of these positions are shown by Socrates
to be flawed in one way or another. They belong to the realm of
uninformed opinion. The remaining books of the Republic seek to
overcome these false conceptions of justice and to find its true
nature.
This
is not the time to explore that in detail. But one thing ought to
be noted. Platos dialogue arrives at an understanding that,
through erroneous thinking, Nature and Law have become separated.
The Greek words are physis and nomos. For Plato the
law of anything is its nature, or its nature is its law. This law
belonging to each thing is also its natural connection with all
other things. The whole cosmos is a harmony between all its parts,
and this harmony is the coincidence of physis and nomos,
Nature and Law.
The
Greek word kosmos means order. Everything has
a part to play within the great whole, and through performing that
part each fulfils its own being. It becomes harmonious with itself
and with the whole cosmos. This harmonious order of things is true
justice. Justice is not imposed upon things from outside but belongs
to their essence and their proper mode of being. It means each thing
acts according to its own true nature when it acts according to
the order of the whole. It also means that each human being who
lives justly has a harmonious order in their own being or soul,
so that thought, action and virtue all work together. Most important
of all, living justly becomes the primary aim of human life, both
within and without. Next after that is the health of the body, and
lastly the right use of wealth.
For
Plato and for Aristotle, a life devoted to gathering money or wealth
is quite simply an ignoble life. This is especially clear in Aristotle.
In his Politics he argues that nature is ordered in such
a way that the needs of all creatures are fully met. The land naturally
supplies enough for a human community, and there is a natural limit
in what it provides. Seeking in excess of this natural limit is
harmful. True economics is an economics of sufficiency, in accord
with what nature provides in due measure.
This
means that trading solely for monetary profit is not only an ignoble
way of life, it also goes beyond the natural limits of natures
provisions. To seek to acquire unlimited wealth distorts the harmony
of nature. It is unjust. The fact that such acquisition has no natural
limit indicates it is unjust, since justice is always proportionate.
But also, for both Plato and Aristotle, trading merely for the sake
of money corrodes the civil order of the community. Markets in this
sense are a threat to the social stability of the polis.
They corrupt natural human relationships. For Aristotle economics
is the study of a society becoming self-sufficient in necessities,
within the limits of nature. It is more a study of good management
rather than of commerce. The aim is health and peace
rather than wealth.
These
two perspectives the Christian and the philosophic
are quite different to each other, yet together they embody the
highest aims of a just society in Western civilisation, which has
absorbed aspects of each. One seeks a way of life based on goodness
and mercy, on the love of God and neighbour. The parable of the
Good Samaritan still strikes a note. The other seeks a way of life
through reason and discriminating between reality and appearance.
It seeks an understanding of the unity of physis and nomos,
Nature and Law, or the real and the good, the truthful and the ethical.
Yet both see the quest for the just life as an ongoing journey.
For the Christian tradition it lies in overcoming the avaricious
desires that come with the Fall, while for the philosophic tradition
it is a way of bringing human nature and society into harmony with
the cosmic order.
These
are the leading responses in our Western civilisation to the injustices
that afflict human society. Yet they both aim at a condition of
justice that seems beyond the capacity of the majority of people.
The Church Fathers and the philosophers were perfectly aware of
this. Those who are wealthy through misappropriating the labour
of others are not that keen on having a just society. They can console
themselves with the belief that justice is an impossible utopian
dream. Those who protest on behalf of the poor are too often driven
by envy of the rich, and so they bring no remedy. Complacency and
anger are two common responses to the question of justice.
Given
the fact that few are likely to become saints or philosophers, is
there a kind of justice that can be established which removes the
worst ills that arise from the misappropriation of the land, and
which opens a way towards the possibility of a truly just society?
Well, obviously at least to us, Henry George opens the door to such
a possibility, by removing the means of misappropriating the land
and stealing the value created by the community and the wages of
those who produce wealth. There are elements of the generous Christian
ethic in Georges work as well as elements from the noble philosophic
tradition, especially that of the Natural Law and the understanding
of justice as a universal principle. There is a tendency nowadays,
unfortunately, to reduce the scope of Georges insights merely
to his fiscal proposals, and to seeking ways of implementing a land
tax, forgetting that it is the love of justice that informs all
his social and economic analysis.
We
are confronted with the simple fact that modern society is as far
from achieving this today as George was a hundred years ago
or the Church Fathers were in persuading the people that the land
belongs to all in common sixteen hundred years ago, or Plato 2,500
years ago. For as far back as we can go in recorded history it has
always been proclaimed by the poets, the prophets and the philosophers
that the earth belongs to all in common. Virgil, for example, writes
of a Golden Age when:
No
tenants mastered holdings,
Even to mark the land with private bounds
Was wrong: men worked for the common store, and earth
herself, unbidden, yielded more fully. (Georgics I/126-29)
And
the great Roman poet Ovid writes:
The
earth itself, which before had been, like air and sunshine,
A treasure for all to share, was now crisscrossed with lines
Men measured and marked with boundary posts and fences. (Metamorphosis
I/134-36)
The
Stoic philosopher Seneca also writes of the Golden Age:
The
social virtues had remained pure and inviolate before covetousness
distracted society and introduced poverty, for men ceased to possess
all things when they began to call anything their own. . . . How
happy was the primitive age when the bounties of nature lay in
common and were used freely; nor had avarice and luxury disunited
mortals and made them prey upon one another. They enjoyed all
nature in common, which thus gave them secure possession of public
wealth. Why should I not think them the richest of all people,
among whom was not to be found one poor man? (The Epistles)
Not
only are we far from such visions, we have an added difficulty in
our time, the implications of which were only hinted at in Georges
time: the separation of the economic realm from the social realm.
This is something Karl Polanyi has observed very clearly in his
The Great Transformation. With the growth of a market economy,
aimed at exchange for profit, the creation of wealth has gradually
divorced itself from the social realm, and come to exist independently
of society. Not only is land monopoly misappropriating the natural
community revenue and diminishing the wages of labour, the economy
as a whole is becoming parasitic upon society, making human life
serve the economy, rather than the economy serve human life. This
separation, now so plainly evident, especially in the great cities
where land monopoly is rife, is precisely what Aristotle warned
against, and what the Church Fathers struggled against.
This
separation of the economic from the social is reinforced by the
modern reduction of economic analysis to mathematical models. The
tendency to reduce economics to mathematical calculation was already
present in the early economic thinking of the seventeenth century.
And this in turn came from a previous shift in the conception of
the laws of nature. The new conception of the laws of
nature was based upon a purely mechanistic observation of the laws
of motion, to which all phenomena could be reduced. This new view
was hailed as superseding the religious and philosophical approaches
to nature. These, it was argued, belonged to a more primitive stage
of society, preparing the way for the empirical method of mechanical
science. This idea is expressed in Turgot, for example, one of the
pioneers of economics in the eighteenth century. The Physiocrats
were not immune to the mechanistic thinking of their age through
which they sought to express their insights.
The
expression laws of nature was directly opposed to the
tradition of natural law which extended back to Plato,
the Stoics and early Christians such as St Augustine, and was greatly
refined through the Middle Ages, producing in the twelfth century
the Decretum Gratiani, and culminating in the thirteenth
century in Aquinass great treatise on law in the Summa
Theologica.
Natural
law refers to what we spoke of earlier, the harmonious order of
the cosmos in which everything plays its part for the sake of the
whole. It is the cosmic justice which brings community into being.
It is essentially cooperative as opposed to competitive,
communitarian as opposed to individualistic. Natural law expresses
the common good. According to natural law the land belongs to all
in common, or simply to the Creator as St Ambrose and St Augustine
argued. The new mechanical conception of the laws of nature
cannot account for just possession or ownership. It cannot encompass
commutative or distributive justice. There is no ethical dimension
to the mechanistic conception of nature.
The
new mechanistic conception of nature gets transferred to jurisprudence
with the rise of positive law, which is no longer rooted
in the natural law or a conception of universal justice, but rather
in the will of the legislator. Law became divorced from ethics in
the same way as economics became divorced from community.
It
is therefore no surprise that the expansion of positive law since
the seventeenth century has been primarily in property law. Legally
speaking, ownership becomes the new way of conceiving
human nature and society. Lockes famous theory that the ownership
of land springs from extending self-ownership through labour to
land is the obvious development of this new kind of law of
nature absorbed into positive law. The self-owning person
has no precedent in history. It is rooted in a new conception of
human nature and our relation to the world and society. Out of it
springs a new branch of law called human rights, which
are claims made upon the state, more or less replacing earlier natural
rights, which are natural liberties, as formulated in the
American constitution, which in turn replaced the natural law tradition
extending back into the Middle Ages. This is a mode of law for the
self-owning person, whose claims stand in opposition to the state.
The
modern conception of the state has arisen through the loss of the
communal understanding of society, in which each citizen, through
their specific talents or vocations, serves the good whole. Once
society is conceived in terms of proprietorial individuals, each
seeking their own private ends, then the state in some
form or other has to be imposed to regulate the conflicting desires
and actions of individuals. And this includes the market.
These
are problems that George does not tackle. In his time for most ordinary
people the vision of freedom was still framed within the context
and language of the common good and natural justice, and had not
yet declined into the notion private freedom and individual rights
in opposition to the state or community. It was only the intellectuals
who propagated these ideas, while the majority of people still lived
in the shadow of Christian morality.
Georges
eye is on the just society and on how to remedy the injustices that
arose with the market society based on land monopoly. It may well
be, with the full implementation of the land tax world-wide, that
the separation of the economic realm from the social realm would
be repaired. It may well be that then the pursuit of wealth for
its own sake would be replaced by higher cultural aims, as George
envisioned, including due care for the environment.
All
that may well be so. But the implementation of the land tax will
not come about without first overcoming the prevailing mechanistic
interpretation of economics, which reinforces its separation from
the social realm, and which suits land monopoly by abstracting the
earth into capital or reduces it to mere resources.
Nor can the social good be restored without a return
to understanding the communal nature of the human person. This communal
nature is something that the Church Fathers could call upon when
prompting the rich to share their wealth with the poor. And it was
something that was gradually developed throughout the Middle Ages
through the formulations of civil and canon law, including English
common law.
There
is a growing body of scholarly study of the communal nature of society,
and it is from this perspective that the limited nature of the sphere
of economic theory is clearly brought to light. The study of economics
in relation to other disciplines would be of enormous value. For
example, the very good work being done in environmental studies
and ecology would be greatly enhanced by a good knowledge of economic
and social laws. Environmental destruction and economic injustice
have a common cause. They occur through misconceptions of the nature
of society rooted in the proprietorial conception of our human relation
to the land or nature.
From
the perspective of the Church Fathers and the Greek philosophers,
these are manifestations of the separation of physis from
nomos, of Nature from Law. Where George and the Church Fathers
meet is in their common call for justice in conformity with the
order of nature, and in their recognition of the essential goodness
of human nature.
Given
the Christian interpretation of the fallen human condition, or the
classical philosophical interpretation of our misperception or ignorance
of the true nature of things, how does each tradition conceive a
remedy to the injustice that arises through the proprietorial relation
with the land or nature?
Here
the early philosophers and theologians gave a common answer: that,
allowing for possession by convention, all property ought to be
put to right use. It is not the claim to ownership as such that
matters since, as Avila demonstrates, ownership can only ever be
a legal claim on property. It is how property is used
that ultimately matters. As John Chrysostom says For it is
not wealth that is evil, but the evil use of wealth (p.87).
Lockes
famous argument that we come to own things by extension of our self-ownership
through labour is clearly flawed since we obviously derive our existence
from nature or from the Creator. And why should Lockes principle
apply only to human beings? What of the bird who builds its nest
or the squirrel that buries its nuts? From the perspective of nature
there is nothing unowned remaining for Lockean man to extend
ownership to. St Augustine likewise discounts Lockes argument:
Whence does anyone possess what he or she has? Is it not from
human law? For by divine law, the earth and its fullness are the
Lords (Psalm 23:1). (p. 111)
If,
then, it is only flawed thinking or a legal fiction that makes ownership
seem to be so, and yet through weakness or through ignorance our
society cannot give up the notion of ownership, is there then a
compromise that remedies the injustices that spring from it?
There
is indeed. The compromise proposed by the philosophers and theologians
is to permit ownership but demand right or beneficial use. Whatever
a person possesses ought to be used in such ways as serve the common
good. That was the ethical solution proposed by St Thomas Aquinas,
and he draws it from Aristotle. Nothing in nature comes into being
to be ill-used. Legal possession does not override that natural
law. Good laws, then, are framed to ensure the beneficial use of
things. This is not so strange, as is clear in the modern regulation
of drugs and medicines, or food safety standards. And if this is
right for the use of manufactured things, then how much more so
for the right use of the land itself, the home of all living beings?
When
Henry George suddenly saw how wealth and poverty arose together
through the private monopoly of land he also saw how it could be
remedied through a simple fiscal measure which struck a compromise
between allowing the ownership of land to continue and ensuring
its future beneficial use. This is precisely what a land tax ensures.
Its implementation requires a general grasp of natural justice,
but not that all citizens should become saints or philosophers.
While it would not make citizens virtuous, it would remove practices
which invited vice. It would change the ethos of society from that
of citizens grasping whatever they can through fear of want, to
a general contentment in a visibly just distribution of wealth.
The proprietorial-self would vanish from the conception
of human nature.
|