Economics
and the Common Good
A review of some of the classical and medieval
ideas of social order and justice and an exploration of how they
might suggest remedies to the economic and social crisis of our
times. Lecture delivered to the Henry George Foundation London
2024
Joseph
Milne
The idea of the 'common good' has a long history, going back to
ancient Greece and developed in the Middle Ages. Behind it lies
a conception of an order to society which in some way is part
of the greater order of nature. The idea that there was a natural
order of society and that all its functions and institutions worked
together in harmony to serve the good of the whole was lost by
the fifteenth century. From that time onwards society was regarded
as an artificial construct, with government imposed upon citizens
to curb violence or anarchy. Thus, from the birth of the modernity,
the individual and the state were seen as opposed to one another.
It is an idea that endures into our times, and it hovers over
practically all political debates.
An
opposition has in fact occurred, not between the citizen and the
state, but between the economy and the state. The modern industrial
economy has become divorced from the social and civic life of
society and from the well-being of the whole. With few exceptions,
the wage earner has become an anonymous part of the industrial
machine, while the industrial machine itself has become an anonymous
mechanism dictating international relations. Put simply, the economic
realm has separated itself from civic society. As Karl Polanyi
put it, the economy is no longer embedded in community. The result
is that land, labour and money have all become commodified and
no longer serve the social good. They have each lost their real
nature.
One
of the difficulties we face in economic theory as that classical
'political economy' was born when this divorce was already well
underway and the traditional understanding of society had all
but disappeared. Economic distortions have become so normalised
they are now hard to see.
In the face of this situation I think it worthwhile asking how
an exploration of pre-modern conceptions of society might throw
light on our modern crisis. If we look at Aristotle, for example,
the first thing he observes is that human nature is naturally
social or political. Nobody can live a proper human life outside
society. It is the social nature of mankind (zoon politikon)
that distinguishes man from the other species. For Aristotle,
this distinction is marked by the faculty of speech or logos.
The Greek word logos means both reason and speech. Through
speech discourse on the nature of justice and injustice becomes
possible, giving rise to politics and philosophy. Man is the being
who reflects on the order of things, and this reflection is made
possible through dialogue.
According
to Aristotle, human society is also part of the larger order of
nature. Everything in nature has its natural function and end.
This teleological view shows how everything in nature seeks it
proper actualisation. This is obvious in the biosphere, where
all living things grow towards their completion, and where everything
has its part in the biosphere as a whole. Modern ecology is rediscovering
something of this order in nature which was once universally understood.
Human
society likewise was understood to have a proper end. First, human
nature shares in the ends that all substances seek: the preservation
of their own being. Second, human nature shares in the ends that
animals seek: reproduction and education of offspring. Third,
human nature seeks to know truth and goodness through reason.
These
are shared ends of the individual and the community. Together
they lead to happiness. A correspondence was understood to exists
between the individual and society, or as Plato puts it, between
the soul and the city, psyche and polis. There is
likewise a correspondence between the cosmos and the city
(polis). The same rational order is to be discerned in
all things. This rational order was part of justice, and so a
society can flourish so far as it lives in accord with universal
justice.
For
the Greeks this was attained through arete, which has two
aspects. First, it means excellence, and that any action should
aim at the excellence that belongs to it.
Second,
arete means virtue. This is its ethical aspect. According
to Aristotle, who summarises the Greek view generally, no one
can be happy who is not virtuous. So a major part of Greek education
was dedicated to the cultivation of the virtues of prudence, courage,
justice and temperance. Prudence, or phronesis, means 'right
judgment' in practical action. Prudence grounds the other virtues.
The
purpose of cultivating the virtues was to enable command over
oneself. This was essential to the Greek idea of democracy. Only
those able to govern themselves are free and can contribute to
governing society. Aristotle observes, of course, that the inherent
weakness of democracy is that the citizens may not be able to
govern themselves well. Without virtuous citizens democracy is
unstable. But Aristotle also observes that other forms of government
can work well if the citizens are virtuous. It is not the system
that matters but the character of the people. Good laws are necessary
to the flourishing of society. Good laws have regard to the common
good and commend what is virtuous or forbid the opposite. Aristotle
draws a distinction between the law-abiding citizen and the truly
just citizen. Good laws derive from nature itself.
The
fruit of society considered in this way is justice or equity,
which in turn flourishes in friendship. Plato argues that the
whole purpose of the art of law-making is to bring about friendship.
And a society that lived in true friendship would hardly need
codified laws. According to Aristotle, true friendship exists
only between virtuous people. To live virtuously is to live in
accordance with human nature. Here virtue and freedom belong together.
Freedom is the capacity to excel in arete or excellence,
to be in command of oneself and to develop ones full capacities
in accordance with the common good.
The
defining feature of the Greek city-state is self-sufficiency.
It can provide for all its needs. Self-sufficiency imposes a natural
limit on economic activity. The acquisition of wealth is not an
end in itself. If put first, it leads to degeneration. According
to Aristotle, nature does nothing unnecessary. Therefore it provides
sufficient and a little above to sustain life. Anyone who takes
more than they need takes what is provided for another. The proper
end or purpose of wealth is the health of the body. Maintaining
bodily health was itself regarded as a virtue. But health of the
body is for the sake of the health of the mind or soul. Health
of the soul is for the sake of living justly, and living justly
is ultimately for the sake of theoria or contemplation
of truth. Thus each part of society serves its higher parts and
higher aims. The higher aims inform the lower functions. Things
go amiss when this natural order of priorities is lost, especially
if acquiring wealth becomes the main pursuit of a society, because
it will tend to exceed the natural limits of the provision of
nature.
The
Greek understanding of a natural order to society was developed
by the Stoic philosopher Zeno of Citium around 300 BC. With the
Stoics came the expression 'to live in accordance with nature'.
Its emphasis was on the cosmic order, conceived as a universal
reason. Human reason was seen as participating in the universal
reason.
The
Stoic view of cosmic order established the tradition of natural
law, which influenced the development of Roman law, as in the
codes of Justinian and Ulpian. The emphasis of Roman law was to
serve the common good of Rome. On this Cicero is clear. Any citizen
who acts in their own interest before the good of Rome is not
a Roman citizen. He is hardly even a human being. Roman law developed
the conception of universal law, a law shared by all mankind and
applicable in any state at any time. This universal law, which
reason knows intuitively, is adapted in various ways by different
peoples or states. It cannot be broken. It is universal justice.
It brings its own retribution without the need of human law. In
this sense it is like the ancient Greek goddess Díki, at
once cosmic justice and retribution.
This
conception of universal law, later known simply as Natural Law,
is the law in the order of nature which guides all things to their
proper ends and fulfilment. It is a teleological law. It is almost
indistinguishable from Providence as described by Boethius and
the Neoplatonic philosopher Plotinus. As providence it means that
all things are seen and provided for in advance of necessity.
Hence 'pro-vision'. For example, nature provides food, shelter
and all that the different creatures need. Providence also remedies
injustices by restoring balance. In other words, the universe
is understood to be guided by foresight. It is imbued with intelligence.
That foresight extends down to the smallest things, such as the
right herb to remedy an illness. Everything in nature has its
proper ends and contributes to the wellbeing of all creatures.
It is the original 'ecology'.
From
this comes the concept of 'right use', already present in Aristotle.
The gifts of nature are to be used in accordance with their proper
purpose. This applies to human works, where skills and talents
are given by nature for beneficial ends. The right use of anything
always takes into account its benefit to the community at large.
For this reason there developed a medieval law laying down that
no private property could be destroyed by its owner. Property
law does not confer absolute ownership. The right use of private
property must always regard the common good.
This
understanding of ownership brings us to the medieval Christian
conception of society. Here Roman law, natural law, and biblical
law are all combined. The Greek cardinal virtues were also adopted,
to which were added the Christian virtues of compassion and charity.
In
1088 the University of Bologna was founded by a guild of students
for the study of law. It became a major influence in all law-making
for centuries to come. It gave birth to the notion of 'the rule
of law' over and above any prince of king. All are subject to
the law, while the law itself was rooted in the order of nature
and the eternal law in the mind of God. Human ethics springs from
participation in the teleological order of nature.
Here
an idea found in ancient times comes to light in law. According
to natural law all property is common property, or simply not
property at all. There is no natural right to property. In the
biblical sense, all belongs to the Creator. This meant that private
property can exist only as a legal concept, according to human
law but not natural law. It existed only through legal agreement,
and this agreement was valid so long as it disadvantaged nobody.
All private property must still be used with regard for the common
good. The purpose of manmade property law is to assure its just
use and regard for the common good. It is more a 'right of use'
than a right of ownership.
It
is in terms of the common good that all men are equal in society
under natural law. All share in the mutual benefit of society,
which is a benefit greater than which each has individually. It
is a participatory equality. This medieval notion of equality
is not our modern one. It was rooted in the understanding that
all are made in the image of God and human dignity lies in the
divine image being imprinted in each soul. From this conception
of human dignity comes the concept of human freedom - freedom
being the capacity to act according to truth and for the good.
With Christianity the dignity of the human person becomes central
to the understanding of society.
Medieval
Christianity had another most important influence. The virtues
of compassion and charity led to providing help for the poor and
the founding of hospitals for the sick. It also gradually provided
education for many. The idea of the common good extended into
the idea of service to society. The Church not only worked to
save the souls of citizens, but also to enhance the earthly life.
The theologians held the world to be a supreme good, not something
to be detached from or resigned to as mere fate, as happened in
later Stoicism. On the contrary, the world and the whole of nature
was regarded as a manifestation of the infinite goodness and wisdom
of the Creator. In short, the world was sacred. In the light of
this sacred understanding of the world, medieval sciences began
to be developed. Enquiry into nature was ultimately enquiry into
divine law and wisdom. This attitude further reinforced the idea
that nature should never be abused.
Understanding
the created world as 'good' and 'providential' meant that participating
in society was parallel with participating in the sacred order
of the created world. This in turn led to a special understanding
of education. The purpose of education was to integrate the individual
into society. This meant gradual integration into its various
spheres, from that of the family member, the local community,
the various professions, up to responsibility for society - the
skill of rulership. Thus education was inductive, ascending through
a hierarchy of orders of knowledge and capacities. Hence the famous
Quadrivium and Trivium as seven stages of education.
This
led to founding the cathedral cities. All the professions and
trades had their roles surrounding the cathedral. The cathedral
city was likened to a small cosmos reflecting the greater cosmos.
Within the cathedral itself all aspects of the created world were
represented, from every kind of plant and animal to every kind
of human craft. Thus the sum of all things were gathered into
the cathedral, rendering them all sacred. The cathedral, at the
centre of the city, radiated its holistic influence into the society
gathered about it. This cosmic and communal aspect of architecture
has been all but forgotten in our time.
Community
with a common end is the key to the medieval city. Every trade
and profession served the greater good of the whole. From this
aim arose the guilds of the various trades, which ensured equitable
trade among them and prevention of monopoly. Insofar as they might
compete with one another, it was on the basis of competition in
excellence. No trader could cut prices at a loss to take trade
from another. Nor could usury be established. The guilds ensured
equality and fostered friendship and mutual support. Through learning
a trade one progressed through apprenticeship, to journeyman,
and finally to becoming a self-employed master. Apprenticeship
into a trade or profession was induction into society. Needless
to say, every kind of craft and trade was involved in the building
of the cathedrals. The cathedral united the economy through a
single common aim. The cathedral also united the city of man with
the heavenly city, symbolised as Jerusalem, linking human law
with eternal law.
One
of the criticisms laid at the door of the Greek and medieval holistic
visions of society is that they deny the uniqueness and freedom
of the individual. Karl Popper is one such critic. What the Greek
philosophers and medieval scholars observed, as I noted earlier,
was a correspondence between the individual and society. This
correspondence lay in the fact that the proper end of the individual
was the same as the proper end of society. On this principle Thomas
Aquinas says:
the
same judgment is to be formed about the end of society as a whole
as about the end of one man.
The
question then is, in what sense do the ends of the individual
and of society correspond? Aquinas replies:
If such an ultimate end either of an individual man or a multitude
were a corporeal one, namely, life and health of body, to govern
would then be a physician's charge. If that ultimate end were
an abundance of wealth, then knowledge of economics would have
the last word in the community's government. If the good of the
knowledge of truth were of such a kind that the multitude might
attain to it, the king would have to be a teacher. It is, however,
clear that the end of a multitude gathered together is to live
virtuously. For men form a group for the purpose of living
well together, a thing which the individual man living alone
could not attain, and good life is virtuous life. Therefore, virtuous
life is the end for which men gather together.
Aquinas
here follows Aristotle. The aim of both the individual and society
is not merely to live, but to live well, and to live well requires
living together, and living together requires living virtuously.
In particular this means that both the individual and society
should live justly. Justice is at once an individual virtue and
the ordering principle of society. Individual liberty without
virtue is not an adequate measure of society.
Virtue
is clearly an ethical quality. But there is another meaning to
virtue, as when we speak of the medicinal virtues of herbs or
the good properties of things. Virtue in this wider sense includes
the human gifts and talents. Talents are uniquely individual,
yet can be realised only in society. They are clearly grounded
in the social nature of man. They fulfil the individual and benefit
society at the same time. Hence they are also called gifts. Of
these gifts and talents, Plato suggests that they are naturally
distributed among a community. Cicero likewise remarks that what
one lacks another provides. The gifts and talents of individuals
are the real basis of an economy which embraces society as a whole.
Without society, talents are stillborn. Yet without aiming at
the common good talents may be abused. The understanding that
all things have a right use applies to human talents as much as
it does to the gifts of the earth. Here the ethical and the natural
clearly correspond.
According
to Aquinas, the common good is the final cause of society. As
we saw with Aristotle, everything in nature comes into being for
a definite purpose or end, its ultimate cause. Everything in existence
seeks its own completion. This is an inherent tendency of things.
The good of anything rests in its completeness or full actualisation.
The completeness of society lies in its actualisation in the common
good. The common good is its wholeness. Only through participation
in the common good can the individual citizen enjoy fulfilment
of their own nature.
Seen
in this way, the common good is not simply the sum of every individual
good, but the active contribution of each towards the good of
all. It involves justice both from each individual to each, and
from each to the whole. Only through acting justly in both senses
is the individual truly a member of the community. This does not
mean the individual is subsumed into the community, since each
is consciously and willingly just. Each becomes most fully themselves
in community. To put that another way, "The distinctly human
good, can be properly possessed only as given and received in
community with others."
Clearly
this has economic implications. It implies that any economic enterprise
must act justly within itself as well as towards the whole community.
The acts of justice at the economic level are grounded in the
primacy of the good of the whole. Justice, according to ancient
philosophy, is the universal principle that makes a community.
It governs all relations. This is why Aristotle and Plato argue
that it comes first in understanding the nature of society. Society
arises out of justice, aims towards justice, and is fulfilled
in justice.
Needless
to say, this holistic vision of society was lost.
We
can trace precise historical causes. In the fourteenth century
two new ideas about the nature of things arose. The first was
nominalism, the doctrine that universals exist in name only. The
second was voluntarism, the doctrine that the will precedes reason.
According to nominalist theory, each particular existent thing
comes into being independently, directly created by God. There
is no common nature which they share in, or from which they emerge.
Thus universals such as 'humanity' or 'species', or even 'being',
exist only as names or classifications, not as realities. Nominalism
gradually broke down any conception of integrated order and gave
rise to a purely atomist view of nature and society.
Nominalism
was reinforced by voluntarism, the doctrine claiming that the
divine will precedes the divine intellect, and that it is absolutely
free. Each existent thing is what it is solely by divine will.
And since the divine will is free, it can determine anything and
is not bound by any previous determination. God could change the
ten commandments if he so wished. The 'good' was simply what God
willed.
These
two ideas together caused great confusion in philosophy. For example,
Descartes, in adopting both ideas, says that the reason the triangle
has three sides is simply because God wills it so. He could have
willed differently, and potentially may do so. Hence Descartes
famously could find no ground for intellectual certainty. No necessary
relation existed between mind, perception and knowledge of things.
The
voluntarist conception of the divine will soon became attributed
to the human will. It can choose truth or untruth, good or evil,
simply as decisions of will without consulting reason. Hence arose
the modern conception of 'free will', where freedom is simply
'freedom from restraint'. It is a negative notion of freedom,
with no guiding principle outside the free will. The ancient understanding
of freedom, as we saw earlier, was freedom for excellence, where
the will is informed by reason.
Nominalism
and voluntarism were further reinforced by the denial of teleology
in nature, that is, any principle of final ends. In an atomistic
and voluntarist view of nature an inherent orientation towards
ends becomes inconceivable. 'Purpose' is relegated to human intentions
alone.
These
ideas eventually changed the conception of human nature and society.
With each individual now possessing arbitrary free will, no ground
existed for a consensus of wills. In fact, the idea of free will
quickly degenerated into a conception of anarchic passions. If
consequent social chaos is to be averted, government must be imposed
by those with a more powerful will. This is the thesis of Thomas
Hobbes and the basis of his doctrine of nature as 'war of all
against all'. It combines nominalism, voluntarism and elimination
of final causality at a stroke. It conceives society is an 'artificial
construct', imposed upon an imagined pre-social 'state of nature'.
The ancient understanding of human nature as naturally social
is refuted and replaced by the voluntarist theory of 'social contract'.
Consent of will replaced the ancient conception of a rational
inclination towards justice.
Hobbes
was not alone in propounding these ideas. They were shared by
the natural law theorists Hugo Grotius, Samuel Pufendorf and Francis
Bacon. Law was now 'the will of the ruler', a totally voluntarist
conception of law. From that idea arose the tyrannical notion
of the 'divine right of kings'. The ancient understanding of law
as founded in reason and universal justice was cast aside. These
philosophers and lawyers were perfectly aware of the ancient theories
of society and chose to refute them as impracticable in the present
times.
From
these theories emerged the concept of the competitive society,
a kind of regulated war between citizens where the strong survive
and the weak are weeded out. It took full force in the nineteenth
century in the social theory of Herbert Spencer, but now cast
in the guise of 'evolution' and 'survival of the fittest' - an
expression Darwin adopted from Spencer. The ideology of endless
progress, transformed into social evolution, served to justify
all ills on the way to Utopia and the final dissolution of the
state - a position shared by Marx as well as Spencer. Marx equated
Spencer's doctrine of 'survival of the fittest' with his own doctrine
of 'class struggle'. Social evolution, as either understood it,
was not a work of nature but of human will. It is an ideology
rooted in Hobbesian voluntarism.
Striving
for power and wealth became the acknowledged general aim of society.
And since nothing in nature had an intrinsic value or purpose,
it could be set at human disposal and exploited or abused at will.
Nature ceased being 'nature' and became 'resources'. The private
possession of land became normalised, along with the commodification
of labour and money. Man's relation to the earth became essentially
proprietorial and consequently exploitative.
From
this it followed that the economic realm became entirely dissociated
from the civic and cultural realms of society as Polanyi traces
in his The Great Transformation, mentioned earlier. The
general welfare of society is now conceived as a 'cost' to industry
rather than its natural purpose. The selling of transitory luxury
products takes precedence over health or care for the environment.
The things of higher and enduring worth take second place. It
is thus an inversion of the ancient understanding of the just
order of society and the common good.
The
ancient Greek and medieval understanding of society is, in my
view, a more natural and empirical view of society. It is not
an ideology. It is what would occur if not obstructed, either
by ignorance or injustice. It is founded in a better understanding
of human nature, which acknowledges that everyone has a natural
inclination towards justice and goodness. As Henry George observed,
man is by nature a cooperative species where mutual exchange distinguishes
it from the other species. Aristotle observed that the first exchange
is through discourse on justice. So the quality of any right exchange
is that it should be just. In this view, society is formed from
the top down, according to its final purpose, not from the bottom
up, as has been assumed since Hobbes and Locke. But a society
crippled at the economic level, as is our present industrial society,
which has inverted the natural order, can barely attain any higher
aims that fulfil natural human aspirations.
Seen
from this ancient perspective, George's proposal of a land value
tax takes on a greater significance than it is usually given.
The land value is in fact an expression of the common good which
spontaneously nurtures society. The common good, as we have seen,
exists in those things shared by the community, such as government,
defence, law, the arts, education and civil institutions, all
which serve the community at large. It is because the land value
arising from community naturally belongs to these higher common
functions that it cannot be taken as anyone's private income,
or used for any commercial enterprise.
George
describes how, after the functions of government, it is most wisely
used for communal uses, such as public libraries, parks, sports
facilities, meeting places for the arts etc. In short, for the
cultural life of man, the aims which the economy is meant to enable.
George
comes closest to the ancient philosophers on the questions of
property and distribution of wealth. He observes that from Adam
Smith onwards all economists have failed to recognise that land
cannot be private property according to natural law. In his own
words:
...they all have been from the really great Adam Smith to the
most recent purveyors of economic nonsense in Anglo German jargon
accustomed to regard property in land as the most certain, most
permanent, most tangible.
In
other words, property in land defines the very idea of property
for all these economists.
And
on the distribution of wealth George says in The Science of
Political Economy:
All consideration of distribution involves the ethical principle;
is necessarily a consideration of ought or duty - a consideration
in which the idea of right or justice is from the very first involved.
On
both these questions George would have found agreement with Plato,
Aristotle, the Stoics and Thomas Aquinas. In The Science of
Political Economy there are passages on justice and natural
law that clearly paraphrase Cicero, while in The Condition
of Labour George quotes from Aquinas's treatise on law:
Human law is law only in virtue of its accordance with right reason
and it is thus manifest that it flows from the eternal law. And
in so far as it deviates from right reason it is called an unjust
law. In such case it is not law at all, but rather a species
of violence.
George's
thinking has a greater affinity with ancient philosophers than
it does with the political economists of his own time, which he
generally critiques. His ethics, as with Plato, Aristotle and
Aquinas, always aim at the common good grounded in acknowledgement
of universal law and justice.
|