|
Classical
Natural Law and it's Decline
Part
One
Talk
Given on 19 January 2019 to SPES economics meeting
Dr
Joseph Milne
Let
me begin by drawing a distinction between what is called classical
natural law and modern natural law. This means that the expression
natural law no longer means what it originally meant,
and so when we find the founders of modern thought, such as Thomas
Hobbes or John Locke, using the expression, they are not using it
in the classical sense. They are, in fact, deliberately refuting
and replacing it with a new meaning.
There
is a complex history of how this change came about, but we have
to pass over that for now. The important thing to grasp is that
the classical and the modern conceptions of nature are
completely different. The most important change is in understanding
nature as teleological. The Greek word for nature is physis which
means to grow or to come into being. This
growing and coming into being of things aims at their full perfection,
or full actualisation. The growing towards is the telos
of a thing, the final form it will take when fully actual. This
means that by their nature all things are underway in coming to
the fullness of their being. For example, the child is growing into
an adult, and so if we are to speak of human nature we have to understand
it in terms of the fully grown adult. The same holds for all animals
and for plants. Their nature is to become what they
potentially are, and so their nature includes this growing towards
completion. This means that if we seek to know human nature we must
understand it as reaching out towards its final completion.
This
understanding of nature must be applied to the human community,
or in Greek terms, to the polis, the city. For Plato and Aristotle
the self-ruling city is where human nature may come to its full
perfection. The city, the polis, is the nature of human
community. So the family, the village, and the town all point towards
the city as the complete form of the human community. The city is
the final end of human community, the form that society
takes when it comes to completion. Thus we may say that the town,
the village and the family are parts of the greater whole that is
the city. And it is in anticipation of the coming into being of
the city that the family, the village and the town come into being,
or derive their being; for it is the whole that creates the parts.
According to Aristotle the mark of the complete polis is that it
is self-sufficient and self-sustaining.
It
follows from this that if we are to understand human nature we must
understand citizenship. For the Greek philosophers the citizen
is the fully adult human being. For it is how human
beings act together as citizens that opens the way to the full actualisation
of human nature. And so we find in Plato that his enquiries into
human nature and the virtuous life always involve an enquiry into
the nature of the city, and the enquiry into the nature of the city
always involves an enquiry into the just city. It is only in the
just city that we can discern the nature of the city, for its coming
into being takes the form of completion in justice. Justice in the
city is like health in the body.
It
is worth clearing up a common misunderstanding at this point. Often
the city that Plato or Aristotle speak of are taken to be ideal
cities, and therefore as embodying a political ideology, or suggesting
the best regime. But the word ideal has no equivalent
in Greek, and ideologies are inventions of the nineteenth
century. This misunderstanding is due to reading Plato or Aristotle
as in search of the perfect regime or system of government. But
regimes are secondary for Plato and Aristotle. What they are enquiring
into is the manner in which virtue may flourish, in the city and
in each citizen. Virtue is not a system, not even a
moral code. Rather it is the completed human being, the citizen
who is completely balanced and able always to perform the appropriate
action. The virtuous citizen is in harmony with their own being
and with the human community. The virtuous citizen is then able
to act for the common good, or always act in harmony with the whole
city. This is not an ideology, nor is it established
through any particular regime. It is the classical understanding
of human nature, as citizenship, fully actualised. It is analogous
to the physicians understanding of the fully grown and healthy
organism, or to the musician playing their proper part in an orchestra.
Neither health nor musicianship are ideals or ideologies.
So we need to clear that misunderstanding out of Plato and Aristotle.
There is no word for ideal in Classical Greek.
Because
the citizen represents the mature human being there
is a natural correspondence between human nature and the nature
of the city as a whole, as Plato shows most clearly in the Republic.
The city is the human being writ large. Likewise, the
individual is a microcosm of the city. This means that neither can
be understood independently. As Aristotle remarks, the person who
has no need of the city is either a god or a beast, but not human.
This is not because a person could not survive in the wild, but
because human nature cannot flourish without discourse, without
collective enquiry into truth and justice. It is not quite right
to say the Greeks defined man as the rational being. They defined
man as the being of language, of logos, the speaking being, and
therefore of communal reflection and discourse on existence, as
Plato says in the Timaeus and Aristotle in the Politics. This communal
reflection on existence is the political life. The political
life is the life concerning justice. It is therefore also the life
of law-making. The truly human life is the life of deliberation,
of enquiry into truth and justice. It is an activity, not a system.
This is the nature of the polis. In the classical view, any city,
or any society or people, will approximate this life of deliberation
to one degree or another. Likewise, any city that is in disorder
will be failing in the life of serious deliberation, and therefore
will fall short of its proper end.
From
all this we see that nature seeks full actualisation
of its potential, to fully come into being. At the biological level
we can see this clearly enough. Nature strives for the healthy organism
best equipped to flourish in its natural environment, the biosphere.
But with human nature and society this is not so easily seen or
attained. This is because to see it and to attain it requires enquiry
and deliberation. Human nature must reflect upon itself in order
to become itself. This is a huge leap from the autonomy of biological
teleology, requiring deliberate effort, and a capacity to foresee
the consequences of undertaking actions. With the rise of mind and
thought in the human being there must be decisions on what actions
to take, what truths to hold, and how to venture into the future.
This is the natural world of society, calling individuals beyond
themselves to concern for the whole. It is as much a part of nature
as any other, the natural human habitat. It is here that the question
of how we ought to live arises, and this is the beginning of understanding
natural law in the classical sense. The natural law shows itself
when the question is asked about the place of society in the greater
order of nature or the cosmos. And what emerges is that the city
and the citizen must seek to live in harmony with an eternal order,
or an eternal law, beyond mortal life. This eternal law is the law
towards which mortal life tends.
At
this point we must introduce a concept which has been wholly forgotten
in modern enquires into human nature and the nature of society.
Human nature, though dwelling in temporal time, is open to the eternal.
That is, the human intelligence is aware of eternity and temporality
at the same time. And this awareness of eternity allows us to discern
the contingent. In terms of our enquiry into natural law, this means
that justice is seen as at once eternal and contingent.
Therefore we can make a distinction between a just action and justice
in itself. By analogy, it is like conceiving the perfect circle
and seeing any drawn circle as approximating it. The perfect circle
is the law of any drawn circle. Yet the drawn circle
is an instance of the eternal circle.
From
this we see that a law is not a force imposed upon things.
A society seeks to be just out of its own nature, striving
to approximate eternal justice in contingent circumstances. Here
we must put aside the erroneous Enlightenment idea of law as a force
imposed on things, and even more the doctrine that it is the will
of the ruler. The perfect circle is not a force imposed upon
the geometer. Rather the geometer must orient himself towards the
perfect circle. In this sense he is obedient to the
perfect circle, but through his intelligence seeking perfection.
Likewise with justice. True justice must be actively sought for
it to manifest itself. True justice redeems things,
brings them back to their proper condition from which, through human
weakness, they tend to stray. This is why Plato says that we should
not rejoice when wicked people suffer misfortune through their bad
deeds. Misfortune is not justice. This will make them worse and
lead them into the company of other wicked people, which in turn
will harm the city. Rather they should be redeemed through education
and restored to their proper human condition. This serves both them
in themselves and the common good.
It
is the natural telos of the city to strive to bring itself into
alignment and conformity with the eternal law, with justice. Although
it is its nature to become just, this telos or aiming towards justice
comes from within the city itself and is not imposed on it from
outside. It is the same with the individual citizen, who must strive
to become virtuous since this cannot be imposed from outside. Courage,
prudence, temperance and justice cannot be enforced upon a person
or a city. These must be admired and honoured if they are to be
cultivated. They are rather like latent talents, waiting to be nurtured,
and which will flourish only through deliberate exercise.
Since
justice does not impose itself upon the individual citizen or society,
it must be loved in order for it to be realised. The love of justice
is natural, just as the love of being or of truth or beauty are
natural. This is why Plato suggests in the Laws that citizens should
be educated in such a manner as brings them to love the law and
justice. The love of justice blossoms into the love of the common
good, which is the natural ground of citizenship. A society will
flourish only so far as it seeks the common good, and it is only
the common good that assures individual good. Indeed, it will be
a society only so far as it seeks the common good. And out of seeking
the common good comes friendship. This is why Plato and Aristotle
hold friendship in such high esteem. For Plato friendship is the
final end of the law, the purpose the law-maker has in view when
making a law. For Aristotle friendship in its highest sense is the
love of the good in the friend. Such friendship can exist only between
good people. Such people are true citizens in the highest sense.
This,
then, is the classical understanding of the telos of human nature
and of the city, the natural habitat for the human being. The telos
is the law of their being, the natural law. It is at once the orientation
of their inner order and their orientation to the cosmic order.
Likewise, it is simultaneously grounded in the temporal realm of
becoming, and the eternal realm of pure being. Human nature stands
between these two realms, accountable to itself for its own integrity
and yet measured before eternity. And because it dwells in the between,
the metaxy, the eternal and the temporal, or the immortal and the
mortal, it is always underway, always in question, always called
to itself and beyond itself.
We
begin to see that natural law is not a code that can
be laid down. What can be laid down are reasoned regulations which
reflect the law, or embody the spirit of the law. These in turn
may take the form of conventions. Plato and Aristotle both recognise
how customs or conventions unite a city and root it in a history.
Examples are weights and measures. In trading these are important
and assure just exchange. But different cities will have their own
measures, just as they will have their own currencies. These are
conventions and may be codified into laws. Now one of the disputes
in Platos time was over the meaning of the word nomos, the
Greek word for law, which does not quite mean what our
word law means. As the philosopher Voegelin observes
in his discussion of Platos Laws: Platos nomos,
however, is deeply imbedded in the myth of nature and has an amplitude
of meaning that embraces the cosmic order, festival rites, and musical
forms.[1] Some sophists held that all nomoi or laws
were conventions, and that nature, or physis lay outside
all societal laws. And so the word nomos became ambiguous. Thus
law and nature became divorced from one
another. And still modern scholars often translate nomos as convention.
Now
this divorce between nature and law prevails in our times, insofar
as the modern school of cultural relativism claims that
the ethical norms of any society are only conventions, and that
there is no universal ethics, or universal justice. On the contrary,
all conceptions of justice and law are historically relative or
conditioned. In its modern formulation this idea goes back to Thomas
Hobbes, and with it comes the belief that all laws must be imposed
upon a society by a sovereign power, or sovereign will, man being
socially lawless by nature, in order to ensure peace between naturally
warring citizens. And so emerged the idea that law was the will
of the ruler. One thing that is perfectly clear in Plato and
in Aristotle, and in the Stoics also, is that law is
not anyones will, and this is rather a definition
of tyranny than of natural law or the rule of justice.
This
is a very tricky knot to untie. Think, for example, how on the one
hand many now believe in ethical relativism, or in private
morality, while on the other hand appealing to universal human
rights. This kind of contradiction is due to there being no concept
of natural order belonging to society. It leads to the
notion of one morality for private life and another for public life
another notion defended by the Sophists. And also, as Simone
Weil astutely observed, the modern notion of human rights
gives no definition of the human person or of human
nature. Indeed, she argues that codifying human rights dehumanises
the person into a mere legal entity.
In
this tangle of ideas there is little scope for an enquiry into natural
law. However, we may observe that this kind of difficulty may arise
in any society and any civilisation. There descends a cloud of forgetfulness
of universal order and of human nature, and an effort is required
to recover it. There is no question that Platos political
writings are a response to a crisis of this kind in Athens.
END
OF FIRST PART
[1]
Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume III, p. 271
|
"Moral
acts and human acts are one and the same thing." (Thomas
Aquinas, ST 1a2ae, q. 1, a. 3, c.)
|
|