|
The
Harmony of the Cosmos, the Soul, and Society in Plato
Joseph
Milne
And
the love, more especially, which is concerned with the good, and
which is perfected in company with temperance and justice, whether
among gods or men, has the greatest power, and is the source of
all our happiness and harmony, and makes us friends with the gods
who are above us, and with one another.[1]
Greek
philosophy emerged through speculation on the cosmic myths that
symbolically revealed the divine order of the universe. From these
speculations on the cosmic order arose the various notions of
the elements, the planetary motions and mathematics, and these
notions were related to the question of the human order and the
order of society.[2]
It was understood that the human order was distinct from that
of the immortal gods, yet also distinct from biological necessity.
Human nature dwelled in a region between the immortal and the
mortal, open to eternity yet projected into time, apprehending
the unchanging yet compelled to adapt to the ever-changing. In
the primordial myths the order of nature (physis) and human
law (nomos) arose together and were bound together.[3]
The order of nature and the order of the city resided in the rule
of the gods, and this order could be observed in the harmony and
proportion found throughout the Earth and the heavenly motions.
The cosmos was filled with intelligence and with reason (nous),
and every part and every motion attended the good of the whole.
In
the myth of the Golden Age the human realm and the divine realm
lived in perfect harmony. For example, in Hesiod we read:
The
gods, who live on Mount Olympus, first
Fashioned
a golden race of mortal men;
These
lived in the reign of Kronos, king of heaven,
And
like the gods they lived with happy hearts
Untouched
by work or sorrow. Vile old age
Never
appeared, but always lively-limbed,
Far
from all ills, they feasted happily.
Death
came to them as sleep, and all good things
Were
theirs; ungrudgingly, the fertile land
Gave
up her fruits unasked. Happy to be
At
peace, they lived with every want supplied,
[Rich
in their flocks, dear to the blessed gods.]
And
then this race was hidden in the ground.
But
still they live as spirits of the earth,
Holy
and good, guardians who keep off harm,
Givers
of wealth: this kingly right is theirs. [4]
In
the Laws Plato alludes to that ancient age in which Kronos
‘set up at that time kings and rulers within our cities – not
human beings but demons, members of a more divine and better species
. . . They provided peace and awe and good laws and justice without
stint’.[5]
Yet this could not endure, and men began to devise their own laws,
forgetting the gods and breaking the bond between the eternal
and the temporal. The visible, temporal world may at best embody
the divine pattern, and be regulated by it, and laws ought to
be made as like as possible to the age of Kronos.[6]
This distinction drawn between the eternal and the temporal realms
becomes the birthplace of philosophical enquiry because the distinction
arouses a part of the soul that seeks reconciliation between the
eternal and temporal orders of truth. The eternal realm beckons
the soul, which finds itself dwelling between the two orders,
to enquire into the truth of things for its own sake, as an end
in itself. But once this yearning for truth is born, the mythological
symbols of reality no longer suffice. They were born from primordial
intuition, a form of knowing the essentially true at a single
stroke but which is not yet reflective upon itself. The desire
to understand this truth, beyond simply assenting to it,
is the birth of philosophy.
In
this way, Greek philosophy originated in meditation on cosmic
myth, the primordial apprehension of the whole, with a view to
affirming its truth through reason. And this meditation takes
the form of the question: how may the human being and society
live in accord with the cosmic good? What is the appropriate life
of the human person or citizen? It is at once a rational and a
religious question. For the Greek philosophers, questions of the
explanation of things are secondary to this essential question
that awakens questioning in the first place. Philosophical enquiry
is not a precursor to the scientific explanation of things, because
explanation is not a final end in itself, while the question of
how should life be lived is. And so Greek philosophy, even in
its weaker or degenerate forms, for example, with the sophists
whom Plato frequently challenges in the dialogues, always remains
concerned with the relation of the divine cosmic order and the
order of society or the polis.[7]
The polis and the cosmos are bound together, just as the
polis and the soul are bound together. Greek society drifted
into political decline as it forsook these connections. Thus Voegelin
writes:
In
their acts of resistance to the disorder of the age, Socrates,
Plato, and Aristotle experienced and explored the movements of
a force that structured the psyche of man and enabled it
to resist disorder. To this force, its movements, and the resulting
structure, they gave the name nous. As far as the ordering
structure of his humanity is concerned, Aristotle characterized
man as the zoon noun echon, as the living being that possesses
nous.[8]
And it is with a view to restoring these connections that Plato
and Aristotle enquired into the nature of the polis and
the question of the relation between nature (physis) and
law (nomos). Thus Heraclitus says ‘Those who speak with
understanding must hold fast to what is common to all as a city
holds fast to its law (nomos), and even more strongly.
For all human laws (anthropeoi nomoi) are fed by the one
divine law (theois nomos). It prevails as much as it will,
and suffices for all things with something to spare’.[9]
Hence the nature of the polis and the divine law that sustains
it cannot be separated without causing harm.
Neither
Plato nor Aristotle abandon the gods nor the mythic symbols from
which Greek philosophy was born.[10]
This may be seen in their insistence that virtue and knowledge
are bound together and that only the virtuous soul may contemplate
the truth of things and live in accord with nature. In his Nicomachean
Ethics, for example, Aristotle writes that the contemplative
life is the happiest, as it is the life and activity of the gods:
For
the gods, the whole of life is blessed, and for human beings it
is so to the extent that there is some likeness to such a way
of being-at-work; but none of the other animals is happy since
they do not share in contemplation at all. So happiness extends
as far as contemplation does, and the more it belongs to any being
to contemplate, the more it belongs to them to be happy, not incidentally
but as a result of contemplating since this is worthwhile in itself.[11]
Coming at the close of the Nicomachean Ethics in Book 10,
it is clear that it is only those who follow a noble life of virtue
and excellence have the capacity to participate in the contemplative
life. Contemplative knowledge is a kind of living alignment with
truth, and this is possible only in the soul of the virtuous person
who has self-mastery. In the human realm this relation between
knowledge and virtue is the first harmony, the harmony where the
soul comes into accord with itself and with the divine order of
things. Plato elaborates on this in the Timaeus:
God
invented and gave us sight to the end that we might behold the
courses of intelligence in the heaven, and apply them to the courses
of our own intelligence which are akin to them, the unperturbed
to the perturbed; and that we, learning them and partaking of
the natural truth of reason, might imitate the absolutely unerring
courses of God and regulate our own vagaries . . . Moreover, so
much of music as is adapted to the sound of the voice and to the
sense of hearing is granted to us for the sake of harmony; and
harmony, which has motions akin to the revolutions of our souls,
is not regarded by the intelligent votary of the Muses as given
by them with a view to irrational pleasure, which is deemed to
be the purpose of it in our day, but as meant to correct any discord
which may have arisen in the courses of the soul, and to be our
ally in bringing her into harmony and agreement with herself;
and rhythm too was given by them for the same reason, on account
of the irregular and graceless ways which prevail among mankind
generally, and to help us against them.[12]
Yet for the soul to come into this accord remains a calling, something
to be worked towards and not something simply given, even though
it is the proper end or telos of human nature.
In
the cosmic myths the relationship between the cosmic order and
the ethical is implicit, because truth and falsehood, and justice
and injustice are bound together in action, just as in Greek drama.[13]
But once the true and the just can be abstractly or metaphysically
distinguished from one another, then their necessary unity comes
into peril. It requires deep philosophical reflection to understand
how they are ultimately bound together and originate from the
Good. Thus Plato writes: ‘Therefore, say that what provides the
truth of the things known and gives the power to the one who knows,
is the idea of the good’.[14]
It is for this reason that Plato is always asking questions about
the essence of things. For it is, according to Plato, only through
knowing the essence of a thing that one can see how it originates
in the good. Likewise, the convergence of the true and the just
in the order of things is the ground of the original harmony that
extends into the cosmic order and into every particular being.[15]
Thus Apollo presides over law and the celestial song of the Muses
and over healing through his son Asclepius. The bringer of order
is also the bringer of law and healing. Plato often likens the
art of the lawmaker to that of the physician.[16]
For
example, while speaking of how people desire only laws that will
please them the Athenian Stranger says ‘Such a provision is in
opposition to the common notion that the lawgiver should make
only such laws as the people like; but we say that he should rather
be like a physician, prepared to effect a cure even at the cost
of considerable suffering.’[17]
Also Gorgias draws a comparison between the physician and
the judge in administering justice, one curing the body, the other
the soul.[18]
Again in the Laws Plato sees judicial penalty as aiming
to restore the soul rather than merely causing it to suffer the
consequences of injustice.[19]
In Laws we also read: ‘This, then – the knowledge of the
natures and habits of souls – is one of the things that is of
the greatest use for the art whose business it is to care for
souls. And we assert (I think) that that art is politics. Or what?’[20]
In the Republic Plato draws a direct analogy between health
and sickness and justice injustice, arguing that sickness and
injustice are alike contrary to nature, while health and justice
are according to nature.[21]
Or as Brill observes: ‘Plato’s infamous employment of the language
of medicine to characterize the work of the laws, language which
we have seen play a critical role in the Republic, is in
part a function of his focus upon the condition of the soul of
the citizen. This is to say that Plato’s therapeutic conception
of law is inextricably linked to his psychology… Plato thus allots
a dual educative/therapeutic function to the law’.[22]
Thus
the step from the primordial mythic apprehension of the cosmos
to the reflective philosophical understanding of the truth of
things, which took place in classical Greece after the age of
Homer, also brings reason into reflection upon itself. This raises
the question of the capacity of human intelligence to know the
truth of things, and so the soul is brought into self-reflection
and self-examination. Self-knowledge, knowledge of nature (physis),
and divine knowledge reveal themselves as distinct orders of knowledge
and yet bound together. We can see this most clearly wherever
Plato raises the question of justice. Those who cannot or will
not truthfully observe themselves, such as Thrasymachus, who in
the Republic argues that justice is rule by the strongest
for their own benefit and gives up and leaves the discussion once
his argument does not stand up to scrutiny, or Meno who likewise
sees virtue as doing what is to one’s advantage and harmful to
one’s enemies, cannot grasp the true nature of justice. [23]
They conceive the just or the good only as what is advantageous
to themselves. They cannot consider justice in itself as it belongs
to the right relation of all things with one another, or as belonging
to the harmony of the soul. Justice for Plato signifies more than
anything else the great harmony that is of the essence of all
things. So to conceive justice as privately advantageous is not
only to mistake the nature of justice but also to divide the human
individual off from the polis, and the polis from
the cosmos. Civil fragmentation or factionalism is one of the
perils of the step from the holistic mythic apprehension of the
world and the human situation to the reflective philosophical
apprehension of things.[24]
There is an ever-present danger of losing the sense of the whole
that belongs to the mythic and cosmic symbolism.[25]
In philosophical reflection, reason must trace a path towards
the whole from the particular, and from the immanent to the transcendent,
as, for example, in the allegory of the cave in the Republic[26]
or the ascent to the Beautiful in the Symposium.[27]
Plato
draws upon the earlier philosophers, as well as the poets, for
the themes that occupy his dialogues. With some he draws out further
what they express only tersely, for example, Heraclitus and Parmenides
while others he strongly disputes, such as the Sophists Gorgias
and Meno.[28]
The great question that distinguishes these different interlocutors
lies in the understanding of the relation of language (logos)
to the truth (aletheia) of things. Speech may be divinely
uttered and inspired or deviously uttered for private advantage,
giving birth either to order and friendship, or to chaos and tyranny.
For Plato there is a correspondence between words uttered and
the truth of things, expressed in the word logos itself
which means at once language and reason or intelligence. To ‘speak
truthfully’ is possible either by divine inspiration, as with
poetic frenzy, or where the soul is in harmony with itself and
perceives the true order of things and can speak their right names.[29]
Such speech arises from reverence for truth or piety and is profitable
to all. The Sophists have separated speech from the logos
of things through false employment of rhetoric. For the Sophists
the art of speech is nothing else than the art of persuasion.
They taught this art to those seeking a successful political career.
In this sense the Sophists are utilitarian and pragmatic. But
to reduce rhetoric merely to the art of persuasion divorces the
logos from truth and from virtue.[30]
There
is, however, a middle place between true Platonic speech and sophistic
speech, and this is doxa or opinion. Doxa is opinion
held without proper enquiry or reflection, or views believed on
hearsay.[31]
Such opinions may indeed be true, or a mixture of true and false.
For Plato and for Aristotle common opinion is insufficient to
establish either the truth of things or the good life. This applies
as much to opinions about the gods, nature or politics as it does
about everyday things. The examination of common opinions plays
a major role in the dialogues of Plato. Aristotle also will often
begin his examination of a topic with a statement of what people
generally believe. There is a strong dialectical element in his
Nicomachean Ethics and Politics which, like Plato,
seeks a path from what seems to be true to what is actually true.[32]
Since this involves an examination of the premises or presuppositions
of one’s own thought it also demands self-examination and honesty,
because the aim is not to establish a new opinion or doxa
but to come into a transformed relationship with truth, to harmonise
the soul with the nature and intelligent order of things.
For
Plato the problem of the truth of things does not lie in correct
or incorrect theories or doctrines, or in true or false statements,
but in bringing the soul into a right disposition towards truth,
ethically as well as intellectually. It may only be open towards
it or closed towards it. Paradoxically, the soul is closer to
truth by a recognition of its not knowing, as we see in
Socrates’ insistence in Apology that “I do not think I
know what I do not know”.[33]
The urge for certainty can be an obstacle because it tends to
reduce truth to mere propositions. What the philosopher seeks
to accomplish is to bring the soul into harmony with itself and
with the cosmic or heavenly order, as in Timaeus 47C.
That
passage in the Timaeus alludes to the Pythagorean concept
of the ‘music of the spheres’ in which the motions of the heavens
form a choir of divine music, which only few can hear, and which
regulates the universe in perfect proportion and symmetry, described
in detail at Timaeus 35-37.[34]
It is a symbolic idea, not to be taken literally, embodying an
understanding of the universe governed entirely by intelligent
order – not as imposed upon it from outside, but as its own living
intelligence. Because it is intelligent harmony it is akin to
the human soul when it is brought into its own proper order.[35]
From this comes the tradition of the soul as a ‘microcosm’, containing
within itself the same intelligence and beauty as the ‘macrocosm’.
The soul is not to be understood as a mere replica of the macrocosm,
but as participating in the same intelligence, just as different
living creatures participate in the same life. Intelligence and
life are universals, just as the ‘numbers’ discerned in the music
of the spheres are universals. Plato took ‘number’ very seriously
and the study of mathematics played a major part in the Academy.
The ‘mathematical’ is a type of learning or knowledge that shows
itself as self-evident, as Plato demonstrates in the Meno
with the slave who could solve a geometrical problem without any
prior knowledge.[36]
Nevertheless, the question of the real nature or essence of number
remains a profound mystery, even though it manifests everywhere
in the forms, symmetry, rhythms and cycles of nature.
But
this passage from the Timaeus refers to an order of another
kind, in which the soul is brought into accord with itself through
the virtues. If the soul is to truly govern itself, as the cosmos
does, then its various powers must be coordinated, and this is
the work of the virtues. The virtue of temperance brings the appetitive,
the spirited, and the rational parts of the soul
into concord, with reason ruling.[37]
But this virtue comes about through the cultivation of the virtues
of phronesis (right judgement), courage and justice. For
Plato, as for Aristotle also, ethics is not based on moral principles
but on the virtues, which are states of the soul being at work
or in action. The virtues are like skills. Temperance refers to
the inner order of the soul, while the other virtues refer to
its relationship with the world while maintaining its inner order.
In the Republic and the Laws Plato assigns to the
cultivation of the virtues the principle concern of education,
not only for the sake of each individual but also because only
virtuous souls can truly become citizens and live in harmony and
friendship. For Plato citizenship and friendship are practically
identical, since friendship and citizenship are sustained by a
common love of excellence and justice.[38]
Friendship is the proper proportion of the polis, resembling
the cosmic order and the law of the gods. Plato speaks of this
in the Gorgias:
Now
philosophers tell us Callicles, that communion and friendship
and orderliness and temperance and justice bind together heaven
and earth and gods and men, and that this universe is therefore
called Cosmos or order.[39]
This passage demonstrates how for Plato the understanding of ‘order’
always bears an ethical meaning, and so the order of the cosmos
is at once a proportional and virtuous order. Likewise, the proper
relation between gods and men is at once proportionate, just and
temperate. We find the same idea in Plato’s Laws when discussing
the ends the lawmaker must seek to attain: ‘When we asserted one
should look toward moderation, or prudence (phronesis),
or friendship, these goals are not different but the same’.[40]
This connection of the proportionate and the virtuous in the order
of nature passes down through the Stoics, Neoplatonists, the Christian
Fathers, and through to the High Middle Ages where it is given
full expression by Aquinas in the Summa Theologica.[41]
There is a particular word, homonoia, which bears this
special sense. It is made up of Greek prefix homo-, which
means ‘alike’ or ‘same’ and nous which means ‘mind’ or
‘understanding’ or ‘insight.’ So homonoia means to be ‘like-minded’
or of common understanding or agreement. Its opposite is stasis,
‘internal division’, which in the political sense means ‘civil
war’ or ‘factionalism’. For Plato these words are strongly connected
with justice and injustice. Justice is a form of harmony and right
proportion, while injustice is a form of discord and disproportion.
This is clear in Republic Book I:
Injustice,
Thrasymachus, causes civil war [stasis], hatred and fighting
among themselves, while justice brings friendship and a sense
of common purpose [homonoia]. Isn’t that so?
Let
it be so, in order not to disagree with you.
You’re
still doing well on that front. So tell me this: If the effect
of injustice is to produce hatred wherever it occurs, then, whenever
it arises, whether among free men or slaves, won’t it cause them
to hate one another, engage in civil war [stasis], and
prevent them from achieving a sense of common purpose [homonoia]?
Certainly.
What
if it arises between two people? Won’t they be at odds, hate each
other, and be enemies to one another and to just people?
They
will.
Does
injustice lose its power to cause dissension when it arises within
a single individual, or will it preserve it intact?
Let
it preserve it intact.
Apparently,
then, injustice has the power, first, to make whatever it arises
in — whether in a city, a family, an army, or anything else —
incapable of achieving anything as a unit, because of the civil
wars [stasiazonta] and differences it creates, and, second,
it makes that unit an enemy to itself and to what is in every
way its opposite, namely, justice. Isn’t that so?
And
even in a single individual, it has by its nature the very same
effect. First, it makes him incapable of achieving anything, because
he is in a state of civil war [stasis] and not of one mind
[homonoia]; second, it makes him his own enemy, as well
as the enemy of just people.
Hasn’t
it that effect?
This
discussion is an attempt to refute the Sophist position that justice
is not a universal principle and that injustice for the individual
may be advantageous. If each individual seeks their own advantage,
the Sophist holds, then somehow all will gain and justice is superfluous.
The Sophist cannot see that strife between the different parts
of the individual soul will follow from any form of injustice,
internal or external. For Plato the individual soul cannot be
broken off from the universal order without harming itself. Hence
justice has the peculiar quality of being at once a principle
(arche) ordering nature as a whole and an active state
of being of the just person. For Plato only the just person really
knows the nature of justice. Or the nature of justice is known
only in its active performance.
As
we observed at the outset, Plato is seeking to articulate in philosophy
what was previously evident in myth where the gods presided over
the cosmic order and in every particular down to the smallest
detail. Thus ‘cosmos’ and ‘law’ were practically identical, as
is clear in the passage from Gorgias above. But with the
rise of early philosophy, which began to consider the cosmic order
in rational rather than in mythic terms,[43]
there also arose various forms of agnosticism, especially with
the Sophists. Here two words already discussed become especially
important: physis (nature) and nomos (law). Originally
these two words formed a single concept, as may be seen in Heraclitus’
fragment B 114:
Thou
who speak with the intellect [xyn nooi] must strengthen
themselves with that which is common [xynoi] to all, as
the polis does with the law [nomos], and more strongly
so. For all human laws [anthropeioi nomoi] nourish themselves
from the divine law [theios nomos] which governs as far
as it will, and suffices for all things, and more than suffices.[44]
For
Heraclitus to speak of the divine law (theios nomos)
is to speak the law that ‘suffices for all things’, including
the laws of the polis that ‘nourish themselves from the
divine law’, and there is no appearance of physis as separate
from nomos. Nature and law are bound together. And the
polis likewise comes into being through nomos, since
human laws take their existence from the same divine law that
governs all things. The human citizen, by definition, is the being
that reflects and deliberates on law, or on justice and injustice.[45]
That is the original philosophical understanding. But later physis
began to be conceived as separate from divinity and nomos
and then the notion arose that human laws (anthropeioi nomoi)
derived neither from divine law (theios nomos) nor from
physis.[46]
Rather, human law began to be conceived as merely conventional,
differing from city to city, with no ground in physis.
Thus arose the notion that individuals could follow their own
nature (physis) and ignore the laws of the polis.
And since the laws of the polis existed only by convention,
the Sophists believed that no harm could come to them through
disobeying them, at least in private if not in public. From this
arose the further notion that the laws of the polis were
made by the strongest and that justice was nothing else than the
rule of the strong over the weak.[47]
While
the Sophists could argue private advantage with this teaching,
for Plato it indicated the decline of Athens and the destruction
of citizenship.[48]
But it also indicated, on a more profound level, the loss of the
symbolic understanding of the order of the cosmos as revealed
through the myths of the gods. The loss of knowledge of the divine
order signified the fragmentation of the human order.
Thus for Plato homonoia, physis, and nomos
form a single complex, and it is the challenge of human reason
to grasp this. We find the same insight articulated centuries
later by Cicero: ‘But those who have reason in common also have
right reason in common. Since that is law, we men must also be
reckoned to be associated with the gods in law. But further, those
who have these things in common must be held to belong to the
same state (civitas)’.[49]
The citizen comes into being through homonoia, oneness
of mind, agreement on a common purpose. Human reason is rooted
in cosmic reason. The flourishing of the polis depends
upon this grounding of the soul in the universal order and unity
of physis and nomos.
One
remarkable way in which Plato conceives the proportionate ordering
of the polis in the Laws[50]
is to limit the population to 5,040 households or extended families.
The land for such a city should be large enough to support its
population moderately, without excess, yet sufficient for defence
against injustice from neighbouring cities, and strong enough
to aid neighbours if they suffer injustices. The number 5,040
has exactly 60 divisors, counting itself and 1, and also is the
sum of 42 consecutive primes. It therefore lends itself to complex
proportionate divisions of functions of the population. This is
not the place to elaborate on the special characteristics of this
number. But the notion of a natural size of a self-sufficient
polis which accords with the fertility of the land, the
natural division of the human crafts and due administration of
law, education and religious rites, and is of sufficient strength
to have good relations with neighbouring cities, indicates that
the human person naturally belongs to society. In his study of
Plato’s Republic Voegelin writes: ‘Human nature is conceived
as dispersed in variants over a multitude of human beings, so
that only a group as a whole will embody the fullness of the nature.
Order in society would then mean the harmonisation of the various
types in correct super- and subordination’.[51]
There is a final argument that gives the natural size of the polis
strong support. Such a polis is of a size where all citizens
may know one another and be friends, and this is conducive of
virtue:
There
is no greater good for a city than that its inhabitants be well
known to one another; for where men’s characters are obscured
from one another by the dark instead of being visible in the light,
no one ever obtains in a correct way the honour he deserves, either
in terms of office or justice. Above everything else, every man
in every city must strive to avoid deceit on every occasion and
to appear always in simple fashion, as he truly is – and, at the
same time, to prevent other such men from deceiving him.[52]
Friendship emerges yet again as a principle of harmony promoting
justice, openness and honesty. Human happiness is not attained
through amassing wealth or by taking advantage of fellow citizens
or of other cities or nations. For Plato the economic aspect of
the city belongs to the realm of necessity and is therefore the
least dignified of human concerns. The regulation of the population
to 5,040 where each household has equal land to support itself,
maintained by a prohibition on selling its land, removes the need
for competition or opportunity for exploitation and frees all
citizens to pursue the arts, learning and culture. Plato introduces
another mathematical proportion, suggesting that the difference
in wealth between citizens should never be more than ten times,
and so the realm of necessity does not become an occasion for
strife. Indeed, Plato says the earth must be acknowledged and
honoured as the mother and sustainer of all living beings and
must never be abused. There is a natural apportionment in which
things ought to be honoured:
We
say, then, that the likelihood is that if a city is to be preserved
and is to become happy within the limits of human power, it must
necessarily apportion honours and dishonours correctly. The correct
apportionment is one which honours most the good things pertaining
to the soul (provided it has moderation), second, to the beautiful
and good things pertaining to the body, and third, the things
said to accrue from property and money. If some lawgiver or city
steps outside this ranking either by promoting money to a position
of honour or by raising one of the lesser things to a more honourable
status, he will do a deed that is neither pious nor statesmanlike.[53]
This apportionment of honours corresponds with the cosmic hierarchy,
where the divine intelligence descends through the orders of nature,
ruling things justly and according to their proper ends. In Book
X of the Laws Plato disputes the Sophist view that denies
this divine hierarchy and holds that things come into being instead
by nature, by art and by chance.[54]
This view separates physis and nomos where the laws
of cities are held to be arbitrary conventions devised by art.
It conceives of intelligence coming into being last in the order
of things, rather than first since nature (physis) here
signifies only blind necessity. This view brings the gods into
dispute, or at least their origin. For if the universe came into
being through blind necessity, then the gods can be neither wise
nor beneficent to the cosmos, the city or the soul, but will themselves
be ruled by blind necessity.
From
this state of affairs there arise various positions in relation
to the gods: (a) that they do not exist, (b) they exist but care
nothing for humanity, and (c) they exist and may be bribed into
granting human desires. These positions derive from the belief
that the gods came into being after the elements and the heavens,
and that ‘intelligence’ is an incidental or chance product of
nature (physis), and so all human laws and institutions
have no ground in the cosmic order and exist only by human invention.
It is a consequence of separating physis and nomos.
It reduces physis to a mere mechanism, and nomos
to arbitrary invention, and removes intelligence and justice from
the cosmos – rendering it no longer a cosmos.
Plato
devotes the whole of Book 10 of the Laws to this question,
and how reasoned argument can overcome this false interpretation
of the order of things. It is here where we can see most clearly
how Plato is concerned to recover philosophically what has been
lost or corrupted in the understanding of cosmic myth. The truth
of the ancient myths is no longer intelligible to the Athenians.
The symbols that once communicated the presence of the divine
intelligence in all things, and in the art of law-making, no longer
reveal their meaning. If indeed the universe is ordered by blind
mechanism rather than divine intelligence, then there is no basis
to cosmic justice or justice in civilisation. There is no ground
for preferring a virtuous life to the opposite. And even if the
mechanisms of nature may be discerned through empirical investigation
and calculation, they will have no intelligible purpose or end.
What emerges is a universe with no telos, where things
exist without meaning. Enquiry into such a universe itself has
no meaning.
There
is, however, an alternative approach that Plato takes to the question
of the order and harmony of things. This is through kallos,
beauty. All that is truthful, harmonious, or virtuous appeals
not only to the rational part of the soul but also to eros,
the love of beauty. But just as reason can go astray with sophistry,
so likewise eros can go astray by identifying beauty with
particular objects. In the final speech in the Symposium,
Socrates reports a discourse he had with Diotima on the ascent
of eros from temporal things to eternal Beauty. In the
Phaedrus Plato demonstrates that, whatever we behold here
on earth as beautiful, moves the soul to a great passion because
it is reminded of Absolute Beauty which it once beheld before
coming into the human body.[55]
This great passion is eros, which desires at once to unite
with and to create beautiful things. In the earthly sense it is
the desire for bodily generation, which is to attain a kind of
immortality. But what eros truly desires is not particular
instances of beauty in temporal things, but the Beautiful itself
which is eternal and the source of all beauty. What the soul most
desires is to give birth to the beautiful within itself, to become
that divine Beauty. Thus whenever it beholds the beauty of goodness,
it desires to become good, or in beholding the beauty of justice
it desires to become just, or in beholding the beauty of wisdom
it desires to become wise. It desires both to unite with these
beautiful things and to give birth to them. For Plato truth is
always associated with beauty, and beauty always associated with
goodness, and so the true and the beautiful give birth to virtue
in the soul.
One
of the great questions of philosophy is: how is truth known to
be truth? One of Plato’s answers is that the soul recognises
truth whenever it presents itself. It is an act of anamnesis,
remembering. This is what occurs with the slave in the Meno
discussed earlier. In myth this is the goddess Mnemosyne,
mother of the Nine Muses. Since the intelligence of the soul corresponds
with the universal intelligence, or with the ‘rational motions
of the heavens’ as described in the Timaeus, it responds
through kinship with the universal intelligence. Or, as Aristotle
says in the opening of Metaphysics, ‘All human beings by
nature stretch themselves out towards knowing’,[56]
just as he says in the Nicomachean Ethics that the senses
are oriented towards what is best or most beautiful: ‘. . . since
every one of the senses is at work in relation to something perceptible,
and is completely at work when it is in its best condition and
directed towards the most beautiful of the things perceptible
by that sense’.[57]
This is the ground of reason, and why it is drawn towards truth,
with the senses directed to the same end.
For
Plato it is the same with eros, love. Eros is the
ground of all the different kinds of love, and the root of all
desire or yearning. It seeks to unite with divine Beauty, and
this is the reason why the soul is moved whenever it is struck
by anything beautiful. But in order for it to arrive where it
desires to be, it must learn to distinguish between particular
instances of beauty and Beauty itself. In the Symposium
Diotima explains to Socrates how, upon seeing the beauty
of one beautiful body, the soul must learn to see that it is the
same beauty present in every beautiful body.[58]
The same procedure must be followed with the virtues, and with
institutions, and with laws, moving each time from the particular
instances of beauty to the universal, until it finally arrives
at Beauty itself which has no form, but which gives to all beautiful
things their form.
It
is clear that Plato understands that the truth of things, or goodness
or beauty, can be known only through the ascent of the mind from
the temporal realm to the eternal. The soul is by nature open
to eternity. This is what defines the soul as dwelling between
the mortal and the immortal. If it judges or measures only by
the temporal or finite, then it will never arrive where it seeks
to be and will have only relative or contingent knowledge, or
at best what Plato calls ‘right opinion’. In many ways, this principle
may be demonstrated. For example, we only know the finite by an
intuitive reference to the infinite. Yet the infinite is never
visible. Or we recognise the imperfect because we have an intuitive
knowledge of the perfect. Yet the perfect is never visible. Likewise
with justice or goodness. But also there is a kind of ‘poetic
frenzy’ that embraces the divine, where the mind goes out of itself
in giving birth to beauty:
If
anyone comes to the gates of poetry and expects to become an adequate
poet by acquiring expert knowledge of the subject without the
Muses’ madness, he will fail, and his self-controlled verses will
be eclipsed by the poetry of men who have been driven out of their
minds.[59]
By the constant reference to the eternal or the transcendent,
Plato opens the door to a philosophical understanding of what
was previously established through cosmic myths and the gods.
Yet, as is clear in Book X of the Laws, piety towards the
gods remains essential if the harmony of the polis is to
be maintained. The proper life of the city, which brings harmony
to the soul, is possible only so far as the civil laws derive
from the harmonious order of the universe permeated by divine
intelligence. It is this divine intelligence that manifests in
number and proportion everywhere, and in the providential laws
that nourish life and draw human intelligence, through awakening
eros, towards the contemplation of truth.
Bibliography
Aquinas,
Thomas, Summa Theologica,4 Vols., (London, Second and Revised
Edition, Literally translated by Fathers of the English Dominican
Province, London Burns, Oates and Washbourne, 1920)
Aristotle,
Aristotle's Politics translated by Carnes Lord (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2013).
Aristotle,
Politics translated by Joe Sachs (Newbury MA: Focus Publishing,
2012).
Aristotle,
Metaphysics, translated by Joe Sachs (Santa Fe, New Mexico:
Green Lion Press, 2002).
Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics translated by Joe Sachs (Newbury MA:
Focus Publishing, 2002).
David
Albertson, Mathematical Theologies: Nicholas of Cusa and the
Legacy of Thierry of Chartres (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2014).
Garett
Barden and Tim Murphy, Law and Justice in Community (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010).
Seth
Benardete, Plato's ‘Laws’: The Discovery of Being (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2001).
Sandrine
Berges, Plato on Virtue and the Law (London/New York: Continuum
Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2011).
Mark
Blitz, Plato's Political Philosophy (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 2010).
Christopher
Bobonich, Plato's Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
Eva
Brann, The Music of ‘The Republic’: Essays on Socrates' Conversations
and Plato's Writings (Philadelphia: Paul Dry Books 2004).
Sara
Brill , Plato on the Limits of Human Life (Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press, 2013).
Ronna
Burger, Aristotle's Dialogue with Socrates: On the Nicomachean
Ethics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008).
Gabriela
Roxana Carone, Plato's Cosmology and its Ethical Dimensions
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).
Susan
D. Collins, Aristotle and the Rediscovery of Citizenship
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2006).
John
M. Cooper, Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays on Ancient
Philosophy (New York: Princeton University Press, 2004).
Kevin
M. Crotty, The City-State of the Soul: Constituting the Self
in Plato’s Republic (New York: Lexington Books, 2016).
Mircea
Eliade, The Sacred and the Profane: The Nature of Religion
(New York: Harvest Book, 1959).
G.
R. F. Ferrari, City and Soul in Plato's Republic (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2005).
David
Fideler, Restoring
the Soul of the World: Our Living Bond with Nature’s Intelligence
(Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions, 2013).
Jill
Frank, Poetic Justice: Rereading Plato’s Republic (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2018).
H.
and H. A. Frankfort; John Wilson and Thorkild Jacobson,
Before Philosophy (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Books, 1973).
Michael
Gagarin, Early Greek Law (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1989).
Harald
Haarmann, Plato’s Ideal of the Common Good (Frankfurt am
Main: Peter Lang, 2017).
Max
Hamburger, The Awakening of Western Legal Thought, translated
by Bernard Mial (New York: Biblo and Tannen, 1969) p. 9
Martin
Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1987).
Hesiod,
Works and Days, translated by Dorothea Wender (Harmondsworth,
UK: Penguin Books, 1979).
John
Von Heyking and Richard Avramenko, eds., Friendship and Politics:
Essays in Political Thought (Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press, 2008).
Glenn
Hughes, Transcendence and History: The Search for Ultimacy
from Ancient Societies to Postmodernity (Columbia: University
of Missouri Press, 2003).
T.
K. Johansen, Plato’s Natural Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004).
Jacob
Klein, A Commentary on Plato's Meno (Chapel Hill: University
of North Carolina Press, 2012).
Richard
Kraut, Aristotle on the Human Good (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1991).
Lane,
Melissa, The Birth of Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2014).
Jonathan
Lear, Aristotle: The Desire to Understand (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011).
A.
G. Long, ed., Plato and the Stoics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press 2013).
Glenn
Morrow, Plato’s Cretan City: A Historical Interpretation of
the Laws (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1960).
Alexander
P. D. Mourelatos, The Presocratics: A Collection of Critical
Essays (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1974).
Naddaf,
Gerard, The Greek Concept of Nature (New York: State University
of New York Press, 2005).
Mary
P. Nichols, Socrates on Friendship and Community: Reflections
on Plato’s Symposium, Phaedrus, and Lysis (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2009).
Michael
Oakeshott, Lectures in the History of Political Thought
(Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2006).
John
Sallis, The Figuring of Nature: On Greek Origins (Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press, 2016).
Lorraine
Smith Pangle, Aristotle and Philosophy Friendship (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Lorraine
Smith Pangle, Virtue is Knowledge: The Moral Foundations of
Socratic Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2014).
Richard
D. Parry, Plato’s Craft of Justice (Albany, NY: State University
of New York Press, 1996).
Pelosi,
Francesco, Plato on Music, Soul and Body (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010).
Plato,
Complete Works, Edited by John M. Cooper (Indianapolis/Cambridge:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1997).
Plato,
Republic, translated by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books,
1968).
Plato,
The Dialogues of Plato, translated by B. Jowett, in two
volumes (New York: Random House, 1937).
Plato,
The Laws of Plato, translated by Thomas Pangle (New York:
Basic Books, 1980).
Lucia
Prauscello, Performing Citizenship in Plato's Laws (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2014).
A.W.
Price, Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford:
Oxford University Press 2015).
Paul
Ricoeur, The Symbolism of Evil, (Boston:Beacon Press, 1969).
Gerd
van Riel and Caroline Mace, eds., Platonic Ideas and Concept
Formation in Ancient and Medieval Thought (Leuven: Leuven
University Press, 2004).
Christopher
Rowe and Malcolm Schofield, , The Cambridge History of Greek
and Roman Political Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2005).
Ford
Russel, Northrop Fry on Myth (New York: Routledge, 1998).
Joe
Sachs, , Socrates and the Sophists: Plato’s Protagoras, Euthydemus,
Hippias Major and Cratylus (Indianapolis, IN: Focus Publishing,
2011).
Malcolm
Schofield, The Stoic Idea of the City (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1999).
Adriel
M. Trott, Aristotle on the Nature of Community (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2013).
Eric
Voegelin, Anamnesis (Columbia: University of Missouri Press,
1990).
Eric
Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, Order and History, Volume
III, (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 2000).
Eric
Voegelin, The World of the Polis, Order and History Volume
II (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 2000).
Katja
Maria Vogt, Law, Reason, and the Cosmic City: Political Philosophy
in the Early Stoa (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
Lloyd
L.Weinreb, Natural Law and Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1990).
[1]
Plato, Symposium, 188a, in The Dialogues of Plato,
translated by B. Jowett, Volume I (New York: Random House, 1937).
[2]
In Book 1 Chapter 3 of Metaphysics Aristotle gives a wide-ranging
account of how the ancient thinkers conceived the origin and order
of things, both of how the gods brought things into being and
later how they conceived various elements, such as air, fire or
water, as being the origin of things. In Chapters 4 and 5 he recounts
how Hesiod, Parmenides, Empedocles and Anaxagoras conceived things
coming into being in various ways. In Chapter 6 he gives an account
of how Plato, following the lead of all these previous thinkers,
sought to give more precise definitions of things, and that there
was a distinction to be drawn between sensible changeable things
and their forms and numbers which do not change, here drawing
upon the Pythagoreans. For a penetrating study of the political
and philosophical conditions of Athens that Plato confronts and
seeks to remedy see Eric Voegelin, Plato and Aristotle, Order
and History, Volume III, (Columbia: University of Missouri
Press, 2000). For an excellent introduction to the emergence of
philosophy in Greece see H. and H. A. Frankfort; John Wilson
and Thorkild Jacobson, Before Philosophy (Harmondsworth,
UK: Penguin Books, 1973). See also Alexander P. D. Mourelatos,
The Presocratics: A Collection of Critical Essays (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1974).
[3]
See Frankfort Before Philosophy, Chapter VIII, pp. 248-262
for an account of how Greek poetry and myth were transformed into
philosophy. See also Martin Heidegger An Introduction to Metaphysics
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1987), pp. 13-17 for an
account of the original meaning of physis in Greek thought.
[4]
Hesiod, Works and Days, translated by Dorothea Wender (Harmondsworth,
UK: Penguin Books, 1979), pp. 62-63, lines 108-130.
[5]
Plato, The Laws of Plato, translated by Thomas Pangle (New
York: Basic Books, 1980), 713c.
[6]
Plato, Laws, 714a.
[7]
The word polis has no exact English equivalent and is often
misleadingly translated as ‘city’ or ‘city-state’. In Classical
Greece it meant a self-ruling people, where every citizen took
part in the political rule of the community, including the making
of laws. In the opening of his Politics Aristotle describes
the polis as the coming together of the family, the village
and the agricultural community into a single ‘natural’ society,
the kind of society that human nature is inherently inclined towards,
embracing the common good through rational discourse, able to
sustain itself without the need of external trade, and strong
enough to defend itself. Its aim is to live virtuously and nobly.
In the discussion of the founding of Magnesia in the Laws
Plato likewise sees the polis as self-sufficient and even
having a natural limit of 5,040 households.
[8]
Eric Voegelin, Anamnesis (Columbia: University of Missouri
Press, 1990), p. 59. For an account of Socrates’ and Plato’s challenge
to political corruption that prevailed in Athens, see Melissa
Lane, The Birth of Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 2014), Chapter 4.
[9]
Heraclitus, Fragment B 114, quoted from Max Hamburger, The
Awakening of Western Legal Thought, translated by Bernard
Mial (New York: Biblo and Tannen, 1969) p. 9, with Greek terms
inserted as given by Voegelin in Anamnesis p, 59.
[10]
Every society has its founding myths and associated symbols, even
a modern secular society, such as symbols of justice, liberty
or sovereignty. Such symbols are also part of the social narrative
or history through which a community identifies itself. A contemporary
illustrative narrative is the materialist myth of progress, with
its symbols of mastery over nature, an atheist narrative such
as Plato critiques in Laws Book 10. In the dialogues, Plato
often refers to or calls upon the presiding gods, even when speaking
abstractly about justice, education or an art. Most dialogues
begin with or imply a dedication to one of the gods or take place
on a journey to a sacred shrine, as for example, in the Laws
where the Athenian Stranger and his companions Kleinias and Megillus
discourse on their way to the shrine of Zeus, or the opening of
the Republic where Socrates goes with Glaucon to say a
prayer to the goddess Bendis.
[11]
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics translated by Joe Sachs (Newbury
MA: Focus Publishing, 2002), Book 10 1178b.
[12]
Plato, Timaeus 47d.
[13]
For a full study of Plato’s understanding of the connection between
cosmic order and virtue as exemplified in the Timaeus and
Critias see T. K Johansen, Plato’s Natural Philosophy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004).
[14]
Plato, Republic, translated by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic
Books, 1968), 508e.
[15]
See Laws Book 10.
[16]
For example, in Laws 684c while speaking of how people
desire only laws that will please them, the Athenian Stranger
says ‘Such a provision is in opposition to the common notion that
the lawgiver should make only such laws as the people like; but
we say that he should rather be like a physician, prepared to
effect a cure even at the cost of considerable suffering.’ Also
Gorgias 478-479 draws a comparison between the physician
and the judge in administering justice, one curing the body, the
other the soul. Again in the Laws 728b Plato sees judicial
penalty as aiming to restore the soul rather than merely causing
it to suffer the consequences of injustice. In Laws 650b
we read: ‘This, then – the knowledge of the natures and habits
of souls – is one of the things that is of the greatest use for
the art whose business it is to care for souls. And we assert
(I think) that that art is politics. Or what?’ In Republic
444c-e Plato draws a direct analogy between health and sickness
and justice injustice, arguing that sickness and injustice are
alike contrary to nature, while health and justice are according
to nature.
[17]
Plato, Laws, 684c.
[18]
Plato, Gorgias, 478-479 in The Dialogues of Plato,
translated by B. Jowett, Volume I (New York: Random House, 1937).
[19]
Plato, Laws, 728b.
[20]
Plato, Laws, 650b.
[21]
Plato, Republic, 444c-e.
[22]
Sara Brill, Plato and the Limits of Human Life (Bloomington,
IN: Indiana University Press, 2013), pp. 168-9 and 173.
[23]
Plato, Republic, 337c; Plato, Meno, 71e in The
Dialogues of Plato, translated by B. Jowett, Volume I (New
York: Random House, 1937).
[24]
For a detailed discussion of the break from myth and the transition
to philosophy in Athens see Eric Voegelin The World of the
Polis, Order and History, Volume II (Columbia: University
of Missouri Press, 2000), Chapter 6, ‘The Break with Myth’.
[25]
On the place of myth and symbol in any society Ricoeur observes
‘The first function of the myths of evil is to embrace mankind
as a whole in one ideal history. By means of a time that represents
all times, ‘man’ is manifested as a concrete universal; Adam signifies
man. ‘In’ Adam, says Saint Paul, we have all sinned. Thus experience
escapes its singularity; it is transmuted in its own ‘archetype’.
Through the figure of the hero, the ancestor, the Titan, the first
man, the demigod, experience is put on the track of existential
structures: one can now say man, existence, human being,
because in the myth the human type is recapitulated, summed up.
See Paul Ricoeur, The Symbolism of Evil, (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1969), p. 162. Also see Ford Russel, Northrop Frye on
Myth (New York: Routledge, 1998), Chapter 14, ‘Ricoeur
and Fry on Myth’.
[26]
Plato, Republic, 514a–520a.
[27]
Plato, Symposium 201d-207a.
[28]
For a valuable historical and philosophical discussion of the
relation of Parmenides and Heraclitus to Plato See Voegelin, The
World of the Polis, Chapters 8 and 9, and for the Sophists
see Chapter 11. See also Mourelatos The Presocratics.
[29]
For frenzy see, for example, Plato’s Phaedrus.
[30]
For a valuable discussion of Plato’s views on the Sophists see
the ‘Introduction’ in Joe Sachs, Socrates and the Sophists:
Plato’s Protagoras, Euthydemus, Hippias Major and Cratylus
(Indianapolis, IN: Focus Publishing, 2011).
[31]
See, for example, Laws 899d – 902c on false or misguided
opinions about the gods. For a detailed discussion of the special
meaning of doxa in Parmenides and the shaping of
Plato’s philosophy of being see Voegelin The World of the Polis
Chapter 8, especially p. 285ff.
[32]
In the Politics 1252A Aristotle argues that those who claim
that skill in political rule is the same as household management
or mastery of slaves, but on a larger scale, ‘do not speak beautifully’.
As Sachs remarks on this passage in note 39, ‘the same assumption
is made by the Eleatic Stranger at the beginning of Plato’s Statesman
(258E-258C)’. The classic example of the movement from appearance
to the true is the allegory of the Cave in Republic 514a–520a.
[33]
Plato, Apology 21-22 in Plato: Complete Works, translated
by G. M. A. Grubb (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997).
[34]
For a valuable study of this tradition see S. K. Heninger, Touches
of Sweet Harmony (Tacoma, WA: Angelico Press, 2013).
[35]
For a detailed study of Plato’s understanding of how the soul
is brought into harmony see Francesco Pelosi Plato on Music,
Soul and Body (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).
[36]
See Plato, Meno 84c-85d. The question the dialogue poses
is whether virtue can be learned and if a distinction can be drawn
between given or innate knowledge and acquired knowledge. That
the slave who can solve a geometrical problem without prior study
suggests, Socrates argues, that certain kinds of knowledge are
already within the soul. Nevertheless, the dialogue comes to no
conclusion as to whether virtue is innate or can be taught. The
final suggestion is that virtue may be a gift from the gods. It
is worth bearing in mind that for Plato it is the enquiry itself
that matters, even if it leads to contradictory conclusions or
no conclusion at all. Through the act of enquiring into the truth
of things the soul already comes into a more harmonious relation
with itself and with the greater order of things. It becomes temperate.
The path any dialogue follows depends upon the condition of the
souls of the interlocutors. This should make us particularly cautious
about drawing fixed theories or doctrines from them.
[37]
Plato, Republic, 441e4-6.
[38]
For wide-ranging study of Plato on friendship see Mary P. Nichols
Socrates of Friendship and Community: Reflections on
Plato’s Symposium, Phaedrus, and Lysis. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2009).
[39]
Plato, Gorgias, 507d in The Dialogues of Plato,
translated by B. Jowett,
[40]
Plato, Laws, 693c.
[41]
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica,4 Vols., (London, Second
and Revised Edition, Literally translated by Fathers of the English
Dominican Province, London Burns, Oates and Washbourne, 1920)
1a. 110-119 and 1a2æ. 90-97. See also on justice, community and
the common good 2a2 æ. 58.
[42]
Plato, Republic, 351d-352a in Complete Works, edited
by John M. Cooper (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing
Company, 1997).
[43]
See ‘The Emancipation of Thought from Myth’ in Frankfort Before
Philosophy.
[44]
Quoted from Voegelin, Order and History Volume II: The World
of the Polis, p. 380.
[45]
Aristotle, Politics, translated by Joe Sachs (Newbury MA:
Focus Publishing, 2012), 1253a8.
[46]
For a penetrating and comprehensive study of the emergence of
physis from earliest Greek thought and its meaning in Plato
see Gerard Naddaf, The Greek Concept of Nature (New York:
State University of New York Press, 2005). For an excellent history
of the rise of law on Greece see Michael Gagarin, Early Greek
Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989).
[47]
In this regard it is worth noting that a unique characteristic
of early Greek law was that it was governed by the citizens collectively
and separately from political rule. Elsewhere laws were usually
imposed upon citizens by a ruling class. See Gagarin, Early
Greek Law. That by Plato’s time it could be thought to
be imposed by the strong for their own advantage, as maintained
by some Sophists, shows how the understanding of nomos
had changed since the time of Homer and Hesiod.
[48]
See Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume III, p. 68ff
for a discussion of how Plato saw the decline of Athenian politics
and how this led him to enquire into the nature of justice and
the order of the polis.
[49]
Quoted by Malcolm Schofield, The Stoic Idea of the City
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), p. 68 from Cicero’s
De Legibus 1 23. There is a clear resonance here with Heraclitus’
fragment B 114 quoted earlier. Also see Katja Maria Vogt, Law,
Reason, and the Cosmic City: Political Philosophy in the
Early Stoa (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008) for an
excellent study of the political and ethical philosophy of the
Stoa.
[50]
Plato, Laws, 737c-738e.
[51]
Eric Voegelin, Order and History, Volume III, p. 164. See
also the discussion of the natural division of labour in the community
in Brill, Plato and the Limits of the Human, Chapter 4,
especially p. 98-99.
[52]
Plato, Laws, 738e.
[53]
Plato, Laws of Plato, Laws 697b.
[54]
See Gabriela Roxana Carone, Plato's Cosmology and its Ethical
Dimensions, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011),
p. 164 ff. for a useful discussion of this argument and its
importance in the Laws, 888e.
[55]
Phaedrus, 244-245, in The Dialogues of Plato, translated
by B. Jowett, Volume I (New York: Random House, 1937).
[56]
Aristotle Metaphysics, 980a translated by Joe Sachs (Santa
Fe, New Mexico: Green Lion Press, 2002).
[57]
Aristotle Metaphysics, 1174b.
[58]
Symposium, 201d-207a.
[59]
Plato, Phaedrus, 245a, in Plato: Complete Works
edited by John M. Cooper.
|
"Moral
acts and human acts are one and the same thing." (Thomas
Aquinas, ST 1a2ae, q. 1, a. 3, c.)
|
|